GOODRIDGE, et al.
v.
DEPARTMENT OF PUBLIC HEALTH, et al.
Suffolk.
MARSHALL, C.J. Marriage is a vital social institution. The
exclusive commitment of two individuals to each other nurtures love and mutual
support; it brings stability to our society. For those who choose to marry, and
for their children, marriage provides an abundance of legal, financial, and
social benefits. In return it imposes weighty legal, financial, and social
obligations. The question before us is whether, consistent with the
Massachusetts Constitution, the Commonwealth may deny the protections, benefits,
and obligations conferred by civil marriage to two individuals of the same sex
who wish to marry. We conclude that it may not. The Massachusetts Constitution
affirms the dignity and equality of all individuals. It forbids the creation of
second-class citizens. In reaching our conclusion we have given full deference
to the arguments made by the Commonwealth. But it has failed to identify any
constitutionally adequate reason for denying civil marriage to same-sex couples.
We are mindful that our decision marks a change in the history
of our marriage law. Many people hold deep-seated religious, moral, and ethical
convictions that marriage should be limited to the union of one man and one
woman, and that homosexual conduct is immoral. Many hold equally strong
religious, moral, and ethical convictions that same-sex couples are entitled to
be married, and that homosexual persons should be treated no differently than
their heterosexual neighbors. Neither view answers the question before us. Our
concern is with the Massachusetts Constitution as a charter of governance for
every person properly within its reach. "Our obligation is to define the
liberty of all, not to mandate our own moral code." Lawrence v. Texas, 123
S. Ct. 2472, 2480 (2003) (Lawrence), quoting Planned Parenthood of Southeastern
Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 850 (1992).
Whether the Commonwealth may use its formidable regulatory
authority to bar same-sex couples from civil marriage is a question not
previously addressed by a Massachusetts appellate court.[3]
It is a question the United States Supreme Court left open as a matter of
Federal law in Lawrence, supra at 2484, where it was not an issue. There, the
Court affirmed that the core concept of common human dignity protected by the
Fourteenth Amendment to the United States Constitution precludes government
intrusion into the deeply personal realms of consensual adult expressions of
intimacy and one's choice of an intimate partner. The Court also reaffirmed the
central role that decisions whether to marry or have children bear in shaping
one's identity. Id. at 2481. The Massachusetts Constitution is, if anything,
more protective of individual liberty and equality than the Federal
Constitution; it may demand broader protection for fundamental rights; and it is
less tolerant of government intrusion into the protected spheres of private
life.
Barred access to the protections, benefits, and obligations of civil marriage, a
person who enters into an intimate, exclusive union with another of the same sex
is arbitrarily deprived of membership in one of our community's most rewarding
and cherished institutions. That exclusion is incompatible with the
constitutional principles of respect for individual autonomy and equality under
law.
The plaintiffs are fourteen individuals from five
Massachusetts counties. As of April 11, 2001, the date they filed their
complaint, the plaintiffs Gloria Bailey, sixty years old, and Linda Davies,
fifty-five years old, had been in a committed relationship for thirty years; the
plaintiffs Maureen Brodoff, forty-nine years old, and Ellen Wade, fifty-two
years old, had been in a committed relationship for twenty years and lived with
their twelve year old daughter; the plaintiffs Hillary Goodridge, forty-four
years old, and Julie Goodridge, forty-three years old, had been in a committed
relationship for thirteen years and lived with their five year old daughter; the
plaintiffs Gary Chalmers, thirty-five years old, and Richard Linnell,
thirty-seven years old, had been in a committed relationship for thirteen years
and lived with their eight year old daughter and Richard's mother; the
plaintiffs Heidi Norton, thirty-six years old, and Gina Smith, thirty-six years
old, had been in a committed relationship for eleven years and lived with their
two sons, ages five years and one year; the plaintiffs Michael Horgan, forty-one
years old, and Edward Balmelli, forty-one years old, had been in a committed
relationship for seven years; and the plaintiffs David Wilson, fifty-seven years
old, and Robert Compton, fifty-one years old, had been in a committed
relationship for four years and had cared for David's mother in their home after
a serious illness until she died.
The plaintiffs include business executives, lawyers, an investment banker,
educators, therapists, and a computer engineer. Many are active in church,
community, and school groups. They have employed such legal means as are
available to them -- for example, joint adoption, powers of attorney, and joint
ownership of real property -- to secure aspects of their relationships. Each
plaintiff attests a desire to marry his or her partner in order to affirm
publicly their commitment to each other and to secure the legal protections and
benefits afforded to married couples and their children.
The Department of Public Health (department) is charged by
statute with safeguarding public health. See G. L. c. 17. Among its
responsibilities, the department oversees the registry of vital records and
statistics (registry), which "enforce[s] all laws" relative to the
issuance of marriage licenses and the keeping of marriage records, see G. L.
c. 17, § 4, and which promulgates policies and procedures for the
issuance of marriage licenses by city and town clerks and registers. See, e.g.,
G. L. c. 207, §§ 20, 28A, and 37. The registry is headed by a
registrar of vital records and statistics (registrar), appointed by the
Commissioner of Public Health (commissioner) with the approval of the public
health council and supervised by the commissioner. See G. L. c. 17,
§ 4.
In March and April, 2001, each of the plaintiff couples
attempted to obtain a marriage license from a city or town clerk's office. As
required under G. L. c. 207, they completed notices of intention to marry on
forms provided by the registry, see G. L. c. 207, § 20, and
presented these forms to a Massachusetts town or city clerk, together with the
required health forms and marriage license fees. See G. L. c. 207,
§ 19. In each case, the clerk either refused to accept the notice of
intention to marry or denied a marriage license to the couple on the ground that
Massachusetts does not recognize same-sex marriage.[4],[5]
Because obtaining a marriage license is a necessary prerequisite to civil
marriage in Massachusetts, denying marriage licenses to the plaintiffs was
tantamount to denying them access to civil marriage itself, with its appurtenant
social and legal protections, benefits, and obligations.[6]
On April 11, 2001, the plaintiffs filed suit in the Superior Court against the
department and the commissioner seeking a judgment that "the exclusion of
the [p]laintiff couples and other qualified same-sex couples from access to
marriage licenses, and the legal and social status of civil marriage, as well as
the protections, benefits and obligations of marriage, violates Massachusetts
law." See G. L. c. 231A. The plaintiffs alleged violation of the
laws of the Commonwealth, including but not limited to their rights under arts.
1, 6, 7, 10, 12, and 16, and Part II, c. 1, § 1, art. 4, of the
Massachusetts Constitution.[7],[8]
The department, represented by the Attorney General, admitted to a policy and
practice of denying marriage licenses to same-sex couples. It denied that its
actions violated any law or that the plaintiffs were entitled to relief. The
parties filed cross motions for summary judgment.
A Superior Court judge ruled for the department. In a
memorandum of decision and order dated May 7, 2002, he dismissed the plaintiffs'
claim that the marriage statutes should be construed to permit marriage between
persons of the same sex, holding that the plain wording of G. L. c. 207, as well
as the wording of other marriage statutes, precluded that interpretation.
Turning to the constitutional claims, he held that the marriage exclusion does
not offend the liberty, freedom, equality, or due process provisions of the
Massachusetts Constitution, and that the Massachusetts Declaration of Rights
does not guarantee "the fundamental right to marry a person of the same
sex." He concluded that prohibiting same-sex marriage rationally furthers
the Legislature's legitimate interest in safeguarding the "primary
purpose" of marriage, "procreation." The Legislature may
rationally limit marriage to opposite-sex couples, he concluded, because those
couples are "theoretically . . . capable of procreation,"
they do not rely on "inherently more cumbersome" noncoital means of
reproduction, and they are more likely than same-sex couples to have children,
or more children.
After the complaint was dismissed and summary judgment entered for the
defendants, the plaintiffs appealed. Both parties requested direct appellate
review, which we granted.
Although the plaintiffs refer in passing to "the marriage
statutes," they focus, quite properly, on G. L. c. 207, the marriage
licensing statute, which controls entry into civil marriage. As a preliminary
matter, we summarize the provisions of that law.
General Laws c. 207 is both a gatekeeping and a public records
statute. It sets minimum qualifications for obtaining a marriage license and
directs city and town clerks, the registrar, and the department to keep and
maintain certain "vital records" of civil marriages. The gatekeeping
provisions of G. L. c. 207 are minimal. They forbid marriage of individuals
within certain degrees of consanguinity, §§ 1 and 2, and polygamous
marriages. See G. L. c. 207, § 4. See also G. L. c. 207,
§ 8 (marriages solemnized in violation of §§ 1, 2, and 4, are void
ab initio). They prohibit marriage if one of the parties has communicable
syphilis, see G. L. c. 207, § 28A, and restrict the
circumstances in which a person under eighteen years of age may marry. See G. L.
c. 207, §§ 7, 25, and 27. The statute requires that civil marriage
be solemnized only by those so authorized. See G. L. c. 207, §§ 38-40.
The record-keeping provisions of G. L. c. 207 are more
extensive. Marriage applicants file standard information forms and a medical
certificate in any Massachusetts city or town clerk's office and tender a filing
fee. G. L. c. 207, §§ 19-20, 28A. The clerk issues the marriage
license, and when the marriage is solemnized, the individual authorized to
solemnize the marriage adds additional information to the form and returns it
(or a copy) to the clerk's office. G. L. c. 207, §§ 28, 30,
38-40 (this completed form is commonly known as the "marriage
certificate"). The clerk sends a copy of the information to the registrar,
and that information becomes a public record. See G. L. c. 17,
§ 4; G. L. c. 66, § 10.[9],[10]
In short, for all the joy and solemnity that normally attend a
marriage, G. L. c. 207, governing entrance to marriage, is a licensing law. The
plaintiffs argue that because nothing in that licensing law specifically
prohibits marriages between persons of the same sex, we may interpret the
statute to permit "qualified same sex couples" to obtain marriage
licenses, thereby avoiding the question whether the law is constitutional. See
School Comm. of Greenfield v. Greenfield Educ. Ass'n, 385 Mass. 70, 79 (1982),
and cases cited. This claim lacks merit.
We interpret statutes to carry out the Legislature's intent,
determined by the words of a statute interpreted according to "the ordinary
and approved usage of the language." Hanlon v. Rollins, 286 Mass. 444, 447
(1934). The everyday meaning of "marriage" is "[t]he legal union
of a man and woman as husband and wife," Black's Law Dictionary 986 (7th
ed. 1999), and the plaintiffs do not argue that the term "marriage"
has ever had a different meaning under Massachusetts law. See, e.g., Milford v.
Worcester, 7 Mass. 48, 52 (1810) (marriage "is an engagement, by which a
single man and a single woman, of sufficient discretion, take each other for
husband and wife"). This definition of marriage, as both the department and
the Superior Court judge point out, derives from the common law. See
Commonwealth v. Knowlton, 2 Mass. 530, 535 (1807) (Massachusetts common law
derives from English common law except as otherwise altered by Massachusetts
statutes and Constitution). See also Commonwealth v. Lane, 113 Mass. 458,
462-463 (1873) ("when the statutes are silent, questions of the validity of
marriages are to be determined by the jus gentium, the common law of
nations"); C.P. Kindregan, Jr., & M.L. Inker, Family Law and Practice
§ 1.2 (3d ed. 2002). Far from being ambiguous, the undefined word
"marriage," as used in G. L. c. 207, confirms the General Court's
intent to hew to the term's common-law and quotidian meaning concerning the
genders of the marriage partners.
The intended scope of G. L. c. 207 is also evident in its consanguinity
provisions. See Chandler v. County Comm'rs of Nantucket County, 437 Mass. 430,
435 (2002) (statute's various provisions may offer insight into legislative
intent). Sections 1 and 2 of G. L. c. 207 prohibit marriages between a man and
certain female relatives and a woman and certain male relatives, but are silent
as to the consanguinity of male-male or female-female marriage applicants. See
G. L. c. 207, §§ 1-2. The only reasonable explanation is that
the Legislature did not intend that same-sex couples be licensed to marry. We
conclude, as did the judge, that G. L. c. 207 may not be construed to permit
same-sex couples to marry.[11]
The larger question is whether, as the department claims,
government action that bars same-sex couples from civil marriage constitutes a
legitimate exercise of the State's authority to regulate conduct, or whether, as
the plaintiffs claim, this categorical marriage exclusion violates the
Massachusetts Constitution. We have recognized the long-standing statutory
understanding, derived from the common law, that "marriage" means the
lawful union of a woman and a man. But that history cannot and does not
foreclose the constitutional question.
The plaintiffs' claim that the marriage restriction violates
the Massachusetts Constitution can be analyzed in two ways. Does it offend the
Constitution's guarantees of equality before the law? Or do the liberty and due
process provisions of the Massachusetts Constitution secure the plaintiffs'
right to marry their chosen partner? In matters implicating marriage, family
life, and the upbringing of children, the two constitutional concepts frequently
overlap, as they do here. See, e.g., M.L.B. v. S.L.J., 519 U.S. 102, 120 (1996)
(noting convergence of due process and equal protection principles in cases
concerning parent-child relationships); Perez v. Sharp, 32 Cal. 2d 711, 728
(1948) (analyzing statutory ban on interracial marriage as equal protection
violation concerning regulation of fundamental right). See also Lawrence, supra
at 2482 ("Equality of treatment and the due process right to demand respect
for conduct protected by the substantive guarantee of liberty are linked in
important respects, and a decision on the latter point advances both
interests"); Bolling v. Sharpe, 347 U.S. 497 (1954) (racial segregation in
District of Columbia public schools violates the due process clause of the Fifth
Amendment to the United States Constitution), decided the same day as Brown v.
Board of Educ. of Topeka, 347 U.S. 483 (1954) (holding that segregation of
public schools in the States violates the equal protection clause of the
Fourteenth Amendment). Much of what we say concerning one standard applies to
the other.
We begin by considering the nature of civil marriage itself. Simply put, the
government creates civil marriage. In Massachusetts, civil marriage is, and
since pre-Colonial days has been, precisely what its name implies: a wholly
secular institution. See Commonwealth v. Munson, 127 Mass. 459, 460-466 (1879)
(noting that "[i]n Massachusetts, from very early times, the requisites of
a valid marriage have been regulated by statutes of the Colony, Province, and
Commonwealth," and surveying marriage statutes from 1639 through 1834). No
religious ceremony has ever been required to validate a Massachusetts marriage.
Id.
In a real sense, there are three partners to every civil
marriage: two willing spouses and an approving State. See DeMatteo v. DeMatteo,
436 Mass. 18, 31 (2002) ("Marriage is not a mere contract between two
parties but a legal status from which certain rights and obligations
arise"); Smith v. Smith, 171 Mass. 404, 409 (1898) (on marriage, the
parties "assume[] new relations to each other and to the State"). See
also French v. McAnarney, 290 Mass. 544, 546 (1935). While only the parties can
mutually assent to marriage, the terms of the marriage -- who may marry and what
obligations, benefits, and liabilities attach to civil marriage -- are set by
the Commonwealth. Conversely, while only the parties can agree to end the
marriage (absent the death of one of them or a marriage void ab initio), the
Commonwealth defines the exit terms. See G. L. c. 208.
Civil marriage is created and regulated through exercise of the police power.
See Commonwealth v. Stowell, 389 Mass. 171, 175 (1983) (regulation of marriage
is properly within the scope of the police power). "Police power" (now
more commonly termed the State's regulatory authority) is an old-fashioned term
for the Commonwealth's lawmaking authority, as bounded by the liberty and
equality guarantees of the Massachusetts Constitution and its express delegation
of power from the people to their government. In broad terms, it is the
Legislature's power to enact rules to regulate conduct, to the extent that such
laws are "necessary to secure the health, safety, good order, comfort, or
general welfare of the community" (citations omitted). Opinion of the
Justices, 341 Mass. 760, 785 (1960).[12]
See Commonwealth v. Alger, 7 Cush. 53, 85 (1851).
Without question, civil marriage enhances the "welfare of
the community." It is a "social institution of the highest
importance." French v. McAnarney, supra. Civil marriage anchors an ordered
society by encouraging stable relationships over transient ones. It is central
to the way the Commonwealth identifies individuals, provides for the orderly
distribution of property, ensures that children and adults are cared for and
supported whenever possible from private rather than public funds, and tracks
important epidemiological and demographic data.
Marriage also bestows enormous private and social advantages on those who choose
to marry. Civil marriage is at once a deeply personal commitment to another
human being and a highly public celebration of the ideals of mutuality,
companionship, intimacy, fidelity, and family. "It is an association that
promotes a way of life, not causes; a harmony in living, not political faiths; a
bilateral loyalty, not commercial or social projects." Griswold v.
Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479, 486 (1965). Because it fulfils yearnings for
security, safe haven, and connection that express our common humanity, civil
marriage is an esteemed institution, and the decision whether and whom to marry
is among life's momentous acts of self-definition.
Tangible as well as intangible benefits flow from marriage.
The marriage license grants valuable property rights to those who meet the entry
requirements, and who agree to what might otherwise be a burdensome degree of
government regulation of their activities.[13]
See Leduc v. Commonwealth, 421 Mass. 433, 435 (1995), cert. denied, 519 U.S. 827
(1996) ("The historical aim of licensure generally is preservation of
public health, safety, and welfare by extending the public trust only to those
with proven qualifications"). The Legislature has conferred on "each
party [in a civil marriage] substantial rights concerning the assets of the
other which unmarried cohabitants do not have." Wilcox v. Trautz, 427 Mass.
326, 334 (1998). See Collins v. Guggenheim, 417 Mass. 615, 618 (1994) (rejecting
claim for equitable distribution of property where plaintiff cohabited with but
did not marry defendant); Feliciano v. Rosemar Silver Co., 401 Mass. 141, 142
(1987) (government interest in promoting marriage would be "subverted"
by recognition of "a right to recover for loss of consortium by a person
who has not accepted the correlative responsibilities of marriage"); Davis
v. Misiano, 373 Mass. 261, 263 (1977) (unmarried partners not entitled to rights
of separate support or alimony). See generally Attorney Gen. v. Desilets, 418
Mass. 316, 327-328 & nn. 10, 11 (1994).
The benefits accessible only by way of a marriage license are
enormous, touching nearly every aspect of life and death. The department states
that "hundreds of statutes" are related to marriage and to marital
benefits. With no attempt to be comprehensive, we note that some of the
statutory benefits conferred by the Legislature on those who enter into civil
marriage include, as to property: joint Massachusetts income tax filing (G. L.
c. 62C, § 6); tenancy by the entirety (a form of ownership that
provides certain protections against creditors and allows for the automatic
descent of property to the surviving spouse without probate) (G. L. c. 184,
§ 7); extension of the benefit of the homestead protection (securing up to
$300,000 in equity from creditors) to one's spouse and children (G. L. c. 188,
§ 1); automatic rights to inherit the property of a deceased spouse who
does not leave a will (G. L. c. 190, § 1); the rights of
elective share and of dower (which allow surviving spouses certain property
rights where the decedent spouse has not made adequate provision for the
survivor in a will) (G. L. c. 191, § 15, and G. L. c. 189);
entitlement to wages owed to a deceased employee (G. L. c. 149,
§ 178A [general] and G. L. c. 149, § 178C [public
employees]); eligibility to continue certain businesses of a deceased spouse
(e.g., G. L. c. 112, § 53 [dentist]); the right to share the
medical policy of one's spouse (e.g., G. L. c. 175, § 108,
Second [a] [3] [defining an insured's "dependent" to include one's
spouse), see Connors v. Boston, 430 Mass. 31, 43 (1999) [domestic partners of
city employees not included within the term "dependent" as used in G. L.
c. 32B, § 2]); thirty-nine week continuation of health coverage for
the spouse of a person who is laid off or dies (e.g., G. L. c. 175,
§ 110G); preferential options under the Commonwealth's pension system (see
G. L. c. 32, § 12 [2] ["Joint and Last Survivor
Allowance"]); preferential benefits in the Commonwealth's medical program,
MassHealth (e.g., 130 Code Mass. Regs. § 515.012 [A] prohibiting placing a
lien on long-term care patient's former home if spouse still lives there);
access to veterans' spousal benefits and preferences (e.g., G. L. c. 115,
§ 1 [defining "dependents"] and G. L. c. 31, § 26
[State employment] and § 28 [municipal employees]); financial protections for
spouses of certain Commonwealth employees (fire fighters, police officers,
prosecutors, among others) killed in the performance of duty (e.g., G. L.
c. 32, §§ 100-103); the equitable division of marital property on
divorce (G. L. c. 208, § 34); temporary and permanent alimony
rights (G. L. c. 208, §§ 17 and 34); the right to separate
support on separation of the parties that does not result in divorce (G. L.
c. 209, § 32); and the right to bring claims for wrongful death and loss
of consortium, and for funeral and burial expenses and punitive damages
resulting from tort actions (G. L. c. 229, §§ 1 and 2; G. L.
c. 228, § 1. See Feliciano v. Rosemar Silver Co., supra).
Exclusive marital benefits that are not directly tied to
property rights include the presumptions of legitimacy and parentage of children
born to a married couple (G. L. c. 209C, § 6, and G. L. c. 46,
§ 4B); and evidentiary rights, such as the prohibition against spouses
testifying against one another about their private conversations, applicable in
both civil and criminal cases (G. L. c. 233, § 20). Other
statutory benefits of a personal nature available only to married individuals
include qualification for bereavement or medical leave to care for individuals
related by blood or marriage (G. L. c. 149, § 52D); an automatic
"family member" preference to make medical decisions for an
incompetent or disabled spouse who does not have a contrary health care proxy,
see Shine v. Vega, 429 Mass. 456, 466 (1999); the application of predictable
rules of child custody, visitation, support, and removal out-of-State when
married parents divorce (e.g., G. L. c. 208, § 19 [temporary
custody], § 20 [temporary support], § 28 [custody and support on
judgment of divorce], § 30 [removal from Commonwealth], and § 31 [shared
custody plan]; priority rights to administer the estate of a deceased spouse who
dies without a will, and requirement that surviving spouse must consent to the
appointment of any other person as administrator (G. L. c. 38,
§ 13 [disposition of body], and G. L. c. 113, § 8
[anatomical gifts]); and the right to interment in the lot or tomb owned by
one's deceased spouse (G. L. c. 114, §§ 29-33).
Where a married couple has children, their children are also
directly or indirectly, but no less auspiciously, the recipients of the special
legal and economic protections obtained by civil marriage. Notwithstanding the
Commonwealth's strong public policy to abolish legal distinctions between
marital and nonmarital children in providing for the support and care of minors,
see Department of Revenue v. Mason M., 439 Mass. 665 (2003); Woodward v.
Commissioner of Social Sec., 435 Mass. 536, 546 (2002), the fact remains that
marital children reap a measure of family stability and economic security based
on their parents' legally privileged status that is largely inaccessible, or not
as readily accessible, to nonmarital children. Some of these benefits are
social, such as the enhanced approval that still attends the status of being a
marital child. Others are material, such as the greater ease of access to
family-based State and Federal benefits that attend the presumptions of one's
parentage.
It is undoubtedly for these concrete reasons, as well as for its intimately
personal significance, that civil marriage has long been termed a "civil
right." See, e.g., Loving v. Virginia, 388 U.S. 1, 12 (1967)
("Marriage is one of the 'basic civil rights of man,' fundamental to our
very existence and survival"), quoting Skinner v. Oklahoma, 316 U.S. 535,
541 (1942); Milford v. Worcester, 7 Mass. 48, 56 (1810) (referring to
"civil rights incident to marriages"). See also Baehr v. Lewin, 74
Haw. 530, 561 (1993) (identifying marriage as a "civil right[ ]");
Baker v. State, 170 Vt. 194, 242 (1999) (Johnson, J., concurring in part and
dissenting in part) (same). The United States Supreme Court has described the
right to marry as "of fundamental importance for all individuals" and
as "part of the fundamental 'right of privacy' implicit in the Fourteenth
Amendment's Due Process Clause." Zablocki v. Redhail, 434 U.S. 374, 384
(1978). See Loving v. Virginia, supra ("The freedom to marry has long been
recognized as one of the vital personal rights essential to the orderly pursuit
of happiness by free men").[14]
Without the right to marry -- or more properly, the right to
choose to marry -- one is excluded from the full range of human experience and
denied full protection of the laws for one's "avowed commitment to an
intimate and lasting human relationship." Baker v. State, supra at 229.
Because civil marriage is central to the lives of individuals and the welfare of
the community, our laws assiduously protect the individual's right to marry
against undue government incursion. Laws may not "interfere directly and
substantially with the right to marry." Zablocki v. Redhail, supra at 387.
See Perez v. Sharp, 32
Cal. 2d 711, 714 (1948) ("There can be no prohibition of
marriage except for an important social objective and reasonable means").[15]
Unquestionably, the regulatory power of the Commonwealth over
civil marriage is broad, as is the Commonwealth's discretion to award public
benefits. See Commonwealth v. Stowell, 389 Mass. 171, 175 (1983) (marriage); Moe
v. Secretary of Admin. & Fin., 382 Mass. 629, 652 (1981) (Medicaid
benefits). Individuals who have the choice to marry each other and nevertheless
choose not to may properly be denied the legal benefits of marriage. See Wilcox
v. Trautz, 427 Mass. 326, 334 (1998); Collins v. Guggenheim, 417 Mass. 615, 618
(1994); Feliciano v. Rosemar Silver Co., 401 Mass. 141, 142 (1987). But that
same logic cannot hold for a qualified individual who would marry if she or he
only could.
For decades, indeed centuries, in much of this country
(including Massachusetts) no lawful marriage was possible between white and
black Americans. That long history availed not when the Supreme Court of
California held in 1948 that a legislative prohibition against interracial
marriage violated the due process and equality guarantees of the Fourteenth
Amendment, Perez v. Sharp, 32 Cal. 2d 711, 728 (1948), or when, nineteen years
later, the United States Supreme Court also held that a statutory bar to
interracial marriage violated the Fourteenth Amendment, Loving v. Virginia, 388
U.S. 1 (1967).[16] As both
Perez and Loving make clear, the right to marry means little if it does not
include the right to marry the person of one's choice, subject to appropriate
government restrictions in the interests of public health, safety, and welfare.
See Perez v. Sharp, supra at 717 ("the essence of the right to marry is
freedom to join in marriage with the person of one's choice"). See also
Loving v. Virginia, supra at 12. In this case, as in Perez and Loving, a statute
deprives individuals of access to an institution of fundamental legal, personal,
and social significance -- the institution of marriage -- because of a single
trait: skin color in Perez and Loving, sexual orientation here. As it did in
Perez and Loving, history must yield to a more fully developed understanding of
the invidious quality of the discrimination.[17]
The Massachusetts Constitution protects matters of personal
liberty against government incursion as zealously, and often more so, than does
the Federal Constitution, even where both Constitutions employ essentially the
same language. See Planned Parenthood League of Mass., Inc. v. Attorney Gen.,
424 Mass. 586, 590 (1997); Corning Glass Works v. Ann & Hope, Inc. of
Danvers, 363 Mass. 409, 416 (1973). That the Massachusetts Constitution is in
some instances more protective of individual liberty interests than is the
Federal Constitution is not surprising. Fundamental to the vigor of our Federal
system of government is that "state courts are absolutely free to interpret
state constitutional provisions to accord greater protection to individual
rights than do similar provisions of the United States Constitution."
Arizona v. Evans, 514 U.S. 1, 8 (1995).[18]
The individual liberty and equality safeguards of the
Massachusetts Constitution protect both "freedom from" unwarranted
government intrusion into protected spheres of life and "freedom to"
partake in benefits created by the State for the common good. See Bachrach v.
Secretary of the Commonwealth, 382 Mass. 268, 273 (1981); Dalli v. Board of Educ.,
358 Mass. 753, 759 (1971). Both freedoms are involved here. Whether and whom to
marry, how to express sexual intimacy, and whether and how to establish a family
-- these are among the most basic of every individual's liberty and due process
rights. See, e.g., Lawrence, supra at 2481; Planned Parenthood of Southeastern
Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 851 (1992); Zablocki v. Redhail, 434 U.S. 374,
384 (1978); Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113, 152-153 (1973); Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405
U.S. 438, 453 (1972); Loving v. Virginia, supra. And central to personal freedom
and security is the assurance that the laws will apply equally to persons in
similar situations. "Absolute equality before the law is a fundamental
principle of our own Constitution." Opinion of the Justices, 211 Mass. 618,
619 (1912). The liberty interest in choosing whether and whom to marry would be
hollow if the Commonwealth could, without sufficient justification, foreclose an
individual from freely choosing the person with whom to share an exclusive
commitment in the unique institution of civil marriage.
The Massachusetts Constitution requires, at a minimum, that
the exercise of the State's regulatory authority not be "arbitrary or
capricious." Commonwealth v. Henry's Drywall Co., 366 Mass. 539, 542
(1974).[19] Under both the
equality and liberty guarantees, regulatory authority must, at very least, serve
"a legitimate purpose in a rational way"; a statute must "bear a
reasonable relation to a permissible legislative objective." Rushworth v.
Registrar of Motor Vehicles, 413 Mass. 265, 270 (1992). See, e.g., Massachusetts
Fed'n of Teachers v. Board of Educ., 436 Mass. 763, 778 (2002) (equal
protection); Coffee-Rich, Inc. v. Commissioner of Pub. Health, 348 Mass. 414,
422 (1965) (due process). Any law failing to satisfy the basic standards of
rationality is void.
The plaintiffs challenge the marriage statute on both equal
protection and due process grounds. With respect to each such claim, we must
first determine the appropriate standard of review. Where a statute implicates a
fundamental right or uses a suspect classification, we employ "strict
judicial scrutiny." Lowell v. Kowalski, 380 Mass. 663, 666 (1980). For all
other statutes, we employ the "'rational basis' test." English v. New
England Med. Ctr., 405 Mass. 423, 428 (1989). For due process claims, rational
basis analysis requires that statutes "bear[] a real and substantial
relation to the public health, safety, morals, or some other phase of the
general welfare." Coffee-Rich, Inc. v. Commissioner of Pub. Health, supra,
quoting Sperry & Hutchinson Co. v. Director of the Div. on the Necessaries
of Life, 307 Mass. 408, 418 (1940). For equal protection challenges, the
rational basis test requires that "an impartial lawmaker could logically
believe that the classification would serve a legitimate public purpose that
transcends the harm to the members of the disadvantaged class." English v.
New England Med. Ctr., supra at 429, quoting Cleburne v. Cleburne Living Ctr.,
Inc., 473 U.S. 432, 452 (1985) (Stevens, J., concurring).[20]
The department argues that no fundamental right or
"suspect" class is at issue here,[21]
and rational basis is the appropriate standard of review. For the reasons we
explain below, we conclude that the marriage ban does not meet the rational
basis test for either due process or equal protection. Because the statute does
not survive rational basis review, we do not consider the plaintiffs' arguments
that this case merits strict judicial scrutiny.
The department posits three legislative rationales for prohibiting same-sex
couples from marrying: (1) providing a "favorable setting for
procreation"; (2) ensuring the optimal setting for child rearing, which the
department defines as "a two-parent family with one parent of each
sex"; and (3) preserving scarce State and private financial resources.
We consider each in turn.
The judge in the Superior Court endorsed the first rationale,
holding that "the state's interest in regulating marriage is based on the
traditional concept that marriage's primary purpose is procreation." This
is incorrect. Our laws of civil marriage do not privilege procreative
heterosexual intercourse between married people above every other form of adult
intimacy and every other means of creating a family. General Laws c. 207
contains no requirement that the applicants for a marriage license attest to
their ability or intention to conceive children by coitus. Fertility is not a
condition of marriage, nor is it grounds for divorce. People who have never
consummated their marriage, and never plan to, may be and stay married. See
Franklin v. Franklin, 154 Mass. 515, 516 (1891) ("The consummation of a
marriage by coition is not necessary to its validity").[22]
People who cannot stir from their deathbed may marry. See G. L. c. 207,
§ 28A. While it is certainly true that many, perhaps most, married couples
have children together (assisted or unassisted), it is the exclusive and
permanent commitment of the marriage partners to one another, not the begetting
of children, that is the sine qua non of civil marriage.[23]
Moreover, the Commonwealth affirmatively facilitates bringing
children into a family regardless of whether the intended parent is married or
unmarried, whether the child is adopted or born into a family, whether assistive
technology was used to conceive the child, and whether the parent or her partner
is heterosexual, homosexual, or bisexual.[24]
If procreation were a necessary component of civil marriage, our statutes would
draw a tighter circle around the permissible bounds of nonmarital child bearing
and the creation of families by noncoital means. The attempt to isolate
procreation as "the source of a fundamental right to marry," post at (Cordy,
J., dissenting), overlooks the integrated way in which courts have examined the
complex and overlapping realms of personal autonomy, marriage, family life, and
child rearing. Our jurisprudence recognizes that, in these nuanced and
fundamentally private areas of life, such a narrow focus is inappropriate.
The "marriage is procreation" argument singles out
the one unbridgeable difference between same-sex and opposite-sex couples, and
transforms that difference into the essence of legal marriage. Like
"Amendment 2" to the Constitution of Colorado, which effectively
denied homosexual persons equality under the law and full access to the
political process, the marriage restriction impermissibly "identifies
persons by a single trait and then denies them protection across the
board." Romer v. Evans, 517 U.S. 620, 633 (1996). In so doing, the State's
action confers an official stamp of approval on the destructive stereotype that
same-sex relationships are inherently unstable and inferior to opposite-sex
relationships and are not worthy of respect.[25]
The department's first stated rationale, equating marriage
with unassisted heterosexual procreation, shades imperceptibly into its second:
that confining marriage to opposite-sex couples ensures that children are raised
in the "optimal" setting. Protecting the welfare of children is a
paramount State policy. Restricting marriage to opposite-sex couples, however,
cannot plausibly further this policy. "The demographic changes of the past
century make it difficult to speak of an average American family. The
composition of families varies greatly from household to household." Troxel
v. Granville, 530 U.S. 57, 63 (2000). Massachusetts has responded supportively
to "the changing realities of the American family," id. at 64, and has
moved vigorously to strengthen the modern family in its many variations. See,
e.g., G. L. c. 209C (paternity statute); G. L. c. 119,
§ 39D (grandparent visitation statute); Blixt v. Blixt, 437 Mass. 649
(2002), cert. denied, 537 U.S. 1189 (2003) (same); E.N.O. v. L.M.M., 429 Mass.
824, cert. denied, 528 U.S. 1005 (1999) (de facto parent); Youmans v. Ramos, 429
Mass. 774, 782 (1999) (same); and Adoption of Tammy, 416 Mass. 205 (1993) (coparent
adoption). Moreover, we have repudiated the common-law power of the State to
provide varying levels of protection to children based on the circumstances of
birth. See G. L. c. 209C (paternity statute); Powers v. Wilkinson, 399
Mass. 650, 661 (1987) ("Ours is an era in which logic and compassion have
impelled the law toward unburdening children from the stigma and the
disadvantages heretofore attendant upon the status of illegitimacy"). The
"best interests of the child" standard does not turn on a parent's
sexual orientation or marital status. See e.g., Doe v. Doe, 16 Mass. App. Ct.
499, 503 (1983) (parent's sexual orientation insufficient ground to deny custody
of child in divorce action). See also E.N.O. v. L.M.M., supra at 829-830 (best
interests of child determined by considering child's relationship with
biological and de facto same-sex parents); Silvia v. Silvia, 9 Mass. App. Ct.
339, 341 & n.3 (1980) (collecting support and custody statutes containing no
gender distinction).
The department has offered no evidence that forbidding
marriage to people of the same sex will increase the number of couples choosing
to enter into opposite-sex marriages in order to have and raise children. There
is thus no rational relationship between the marriage statute and the
Commonwealth's proffered goal of protecting the "optimal" child
rearing unit. Moreover, the department readily concedes that people in same-sex
couples may be "excellent" parents. These couples (including four of
the plaintiff couples) have children for the reasons others do -- to love them,
to care for them, to nurture them. But the task of child rearing for same-sex
couples is made infinitely harder by their status as outliers to the marriage
laws. While establishing the parentage of children as soon as possible is
crucial to the safety and welfare of children, see Culliton v. Beth Israel
Deaconness Med. Ctr., 435 Mass. 285, 292 (2001), same-sex couples must undergo
the sometimes lengthy and intrusive process of second-parent adoption to
establish their joint parentage. While the enhanced income provided by marital
benefits is an important source of security and stability for married couples
and their children, those benefits are denied to families headed by same-sex
couples. See, e.g., note 6, supra. While the laws of divorce provide clear and
reasonably predictable guidelines for child support, child custody, and property
division on dissolution of a marriage, same-sex couples who dissolve their
relationships find themselves and their children in the highly unpredictable
terrain of equity jurisdiction. See E.N.O. v. L.M.M., supra. Given the wide
range of public benefits reserved only for married couples, we do not credit the
department's contention that the absence of access to civil marriage amounts to
little more than an inconvenience to same-sex couples and their children.
Excluding same-sex couples from civil marriage will not make children of
opposite-sex marriages more secure, but it does prevent children of same-sex
couples from enjoying the immeasurable advantages that flow from the assurance
of "a stable family structure in which children will be reared, educated,
and socialized." Post at (Cordy, J., dissenting).[26]
No one disputes that the plaintiff couples are families, that
many are parents, and that the children they are raising, like all children,
need and should have the fullest opportunity to grow up in a secure, protected
family unit. Similarly, no one disputes that, under the rubric of marriage, the
State provides a cornucopia of substantial benefits to married parents and their
children. The preferential treatment of civil marriage reflects the
Legislature's conclusion that marriage "is the foremost setting for the
education and socialization of children" precisely because it
"encourages parents to remain committed to each other and to their children
as they grow." Post at (Cordy, J., dissenting).
In this case, we are confronted with an entire, sizeable class of parents
raising children who have absolutely no access to civil marriage and its
protections because they are forbidden from procuring a marriage license. It
cannot be rational under our laws, and indeed it is not permitted, to penalize
children by depriving them of State benefits because the State disapproves of
their parents' sexual orientation.
The third rationale advanced by the department is that limiting marriage to
opposite-sex couples furthers the Legislature's interest in conserving scarce
State and private financial resources. The marriage restriction is rational, it
argues, because the General Court logically could assume that same-sex couples
are more financially independent than married couples and thus less needy of
public marital benefits, such as tax advantages, or private marital benefits,
such as employer-financed health plans that include spouses in their coverage.
An absolute statutory ban on same-sex marriage bears no
rational relationship to the goal of economy. First, the department's conclusory
generalization -- that same-sex couples are less financially dependent on each
other than opposite-sex couples -- ignores that many same-sex couples, such as
many of the plaintiffs in this case, have children and other dependents (here,
aged parents) in their care.[27]
The department does not contend, nor could it, that these dependents are less
needy or deserving than the dependents of married couples. Second, Massachusetts
marriage laws do not condition receipt of public and private financial benefits
to married individuals on a demonstration of financial dependence on each other;
the benefits are available to married couples regardless of whether they mingle
their finances or actually depend on each other for support.
The department suggests additional rationales for prohibiting same-sex couples
from marrying, which are developed by some amici. It argues that broadening
civil marriage to include same-sex couples will trivialize or destroy the
institution of marriage as it has historically been fashioned. Certainly our
decision today marks a significant change in the definition of marriage as it
has been inherited from the common law, and understood by many societies for
centuries. But it does not disturb the fundamental value of marriage in our
society.
Here, the plaintiffs seek only to be married, not to undermine
the institution of civil marriage. They do not want marriage abolished. They do
not attack the binary nature of marriage, the consanguinity provisions, or any
of the other gate-keeping provisions of the marriage licensing law. Recognizing
the right of an individual to marry a person of the same sex will not diminish
the validity or dignity of opposite-sex marriage, any more than recognizing the
right of an individual to marry a person of a different race devalues the
marriage of a person who marries someone of her own race.[28]
If anything, extending civil marriage to same-sex couples reinforces the
importance of marriage to individuals and communities. That same-sex couples are
willing to embrace marriage's solemn obligations of exclusivity, mutual support,
and commitment to one another is a testament to the enduring place of marriage
in our laws and in the human spirit.[29]
It has been argued that, due to the State's strong interest in
the institution of marriage as a stabilizing social structure, only the
Legislature can control and define its boundaries. Accordingly, our elected
representatives legitimately may choose to exclude same-sex couples from civil
marriage in order to assure all citizens of the Commonwealth that (1) the
benefits of our marriage laws are available explicitly to create and support a
family setting that is, in the Legislature's view, optimal for child rearing,
and (2) the State does not endorse gay and lesbian parenthood as the equivalent
of being raised by one's married biological parents.[30]
These arguments miss the point. The Massachusetts Constitution requires that
legislation meet certain criteria and not extend beyond certain limits. It is
the function of courts to determine whether these criteria are met and whether
these limits are exceeded. In most instances, these limits are defined by
whether a rational basis exists to conclude that legislation will bring about a
rational result. The Legislature in the first instance, and the courts in the
last instance, must ascertain whether such a rational basis exists. To label the
court's role as usurping that of the Legislature, see, e.g., post at (Cordy, J.,
dissenting), is to misunderstand the nature and purpose of judicial review. We
owe great deference to the Legislature to decide social and policy issues, but
it is the traditional and settled role of courts to decide constitutional
issues.[31]
The history of constitutional law "is the story of the
extension of constitutional rights and protections to people once ignored or
excluded." United States v. Virginia, 518 U.S. 515, 557 (1996) (construing
equal protection clause of the Fourteenth Amendment to prohibit categorical
exclusion of women from public military institute). This statement is as true in
the area of civil marriage as in any other area of civil rights. See, e.g.,
Turner v. Safley, 482 U.S. 78 (1987); Loving v. Virginia, 388 U.S. 1 (1967);
Perez v. Sharp, 32 Cal. 2d 711 (1948). As a public institution and a right of
fundamental importance, civil marriage is an evolving paradigm. The common law
was exceptionally harsh toward women who became wives: a woman's legal identity
all but evaporated into that of her husband. See generally C.P. Kindregan, Jr.,
& M.L. Inker, Family Law and Practice §§ 1.9 and 1.10 (3d ed. 2002).
Thus, one early Nineteenth Century jurist could observe matter of factly that,
prior to the abolition of slavery in Massachusetts, "the condition of a
slave resembled the connection of a wife with her husband, and of infant
children with their father. He is obliged to maintain them, and they cannot be
separated from him." Winchendon v. Hatfield, 4 Mass. 123, 129 (1808). But
since at least the middle of the Nineteenth Century, both the courts and the
Legislature have acted to ameliorate the harshness of the common-law regime. In
Bradford v. Worcester, 184 Mass. 557, 562 (1904), we refused to apply the
common-law rule that the wife's legal residence was that of her husband to
defeat her claim to a municipal "settlement of paupers." In Lewis v.
Lewis, 370 Mass. 619, 629 (1976), we abrogated the common-law doctrine
immunizing a husband against certain suits because the common-law rule was
predicated on "antediluvian assumptions concerning the role and status of
women in marriage and in society." Id. at 621. Alarms about the imminent
erosion of the "natural" order of marriage were sounded over the
demise of antimiscegenation laws, the expansion of the rights of married women,
and the introduction of "no-fault" divorce.[32]
Marriage has survived all of these transformations, and we have no doubt that
marriage will continue to be a vibrant and revered institution.
We also reject the argument suggested by the department, and
elaborated by some amici, that expanding the institution of civil marriage in
Massachusetts to include same-sex couples will lead to interstate conflict. We
would not presume to dictate how another State should respond to today's
decision. But neither should considerations of comity prevent us from according
Massachusetts residents the full measure of protection available under the
Massachusetts Constitution. The genius of our Federal system is that each
State's Constitution has vitality specific to its own traditions, and that,
subject to the minimum requirements of the Fourteenth Amendment, each State is
free to address difficult issues of individual liberty in the manner its own
Constitution demands.
Several amici suggest that prohibiting marriage by same-sex couples reflects
community consensus that homosexual conduct is immoral. Yet Massachusetts has a
strong affirmative policy of preventing discrimination on the basis of sexual
orientation. See G. L. c. 151B (employment, housing, credit,
services); G. L. c. 265, § 39 (hate crimes); G. L. c. 272,
§ 98 (public accommodation); G. L. c. 76, § 5 (public
education). See also, e.g., Commonwealth v. Balthazar, 366 Mass. 298 (1974)
(decriminalization of private consensual adult conduct); Doe v. Doe, 16 Mass.
App. Ct. 499, 503 (1983) (custody to homosexual parent not per se prohibited).
The department has had more than ample opportunity to
articulate a constitutionally adequate justification for limiting civil marriage
to opposite-sex unions. It has failed to do so. The department has offered
purported justifications for the civil marriage restriction that are starkly at
odds with the comprehensive network of vigorous, gender-neutral laws promoting
stable families and the best interests of children. It has failed to identify
any relevant characteristic that would justify shutting the door to civil
marriage to a person who wishes to marry someone of the same sex.
The marriage ban works a deep and scarring hardship on a very
real segment of the community for no rational reason. The absence of any
reasonable relationship between, on the one hand, an absolute disqualification
of same-sex couples who wish to enter into civil marriage and, on the other,
protection of public health, safety, or general welfare, suggests that the
marriage restriction is rooted in persistent prejudices against persons who are
(or who are believed to be) homosexual.[33]
"The Constitution cannot control such prejudices but neither can it
tolerate them. Private biases may be outside the reach of the law, but the law
cannot, directly or indirectly, give them effect." Palmore v. Sidoti, 466
U.S. 429, 433 (1984) (construing Fourteenth Amendment). Limiting the
protections, benefits, and obligations of civil marriage to opposite-sex couples
violates the basic premises of individual liberty and equality under law
protected by the Massachusetts Constitution.
We consider next the plaintiffs' request for relief. We
preserve as much of the statute as may be preserved in the face of the
successful constitutional challenge. See Mayor of Boston v. Treasurer &
Receiver Gen., 384 Mass. 718, 725 (1981); Dalli v. Board of Educ., 358 Mass.
753, 759 (1971). See also G. L. c. 4, § 6, Eleventh.
Here, no one argues that striking down the marriage laws is an
appropriate form of relief. Eliminating civil marriage would be wholly
inconsistent with the Legislature's deep commitment to fostering stable families
and would dismantle a vital organizing principle of our society.[34]
We face a problem similar to one that recently confronted the Court of Appeal
for Ontario, the highest court of that Canadian province, when it considered the
constitutionality of the same-sex marriage ban under Canada's Federal
Constitution, the Charter of Rights and Freedoms (Charter). See Halpern v.
Toronto (City), 172 O.A.C. 276 (2003). Canada, like the United States, adopted
the common law of England that civil marriage is "the voluntary union for
life of one man and one woman, to the exclusion of all others." Id. at par.
(36), quoting Hyde v. Hyde, [1861-1873] All E.R. 175 (1866). In holding that the
limitation of civil marriage to opposite-sex couples violated the Charter, the
Court of Appeal refined the common-law meaning of marriage. We concur with this
remedy, which is entirely consonant with established principles of jurisprudence
empowering a court to refine a common-law principle in light of evolving
constitutional standards. See Powers v. Wilkinson, 399 Mass. 650, 661-662 (1987)
(reforming common-law rule of construction of "issue"); Lewis v.
Lewis, 370 Mass. 619, 629 (1976) (abolishing common-law rule of certain
interspousal immunity).
We construe civil marriage to mean the voluntary union of two persons as
spouses, to the exclusion of all others. This reformulation redresses the
plaintiffs' constitutional injury and furthers the aim of marriage to promote
stable, exclusive relationships. It advances the two legitimate State interests
the department has identified: providing a stable setting for child rearing and
conserving State resources. It leaves intact the Legislature's broad discretion
to regulate marriage. See Commonwealth v. Stowell, 389 Mass. 171, 175 (1983).
In their complaint the plaintiffs request only a declaration that their
exclusion and the exclusion of other qualified same-sex couples from access to
civil marriage violates Massachusetts law. We declare that barring an individual
from the protections, benefits, and obligations of civil marriage solely because
that person would marry a person of the same sex violates the Massachusetts
Constitution. We vacate the summary judgment for the department. We remand this
case to the Superior Court for entry of judgment consistent with this opinion.
Entry of judgment shall be stayed for 180 days to permit the Legislature to take
such action as it may deem appropriate in light of this opinion. See, e.g.,
Michaud v. Sheriff of Essex County, 390 Mass. 523, 535-536 (1983).
So ordered.
GREANEY, J. (concurring). I agree with the result reached by
the court, the remedy ordered, and much of the reasoning in the court's opinion.
In my view, however, the case is more directly resolved using traditional equal
protection analysis.
(a) Article 1 of the Declaration of Rights, as amended by art. 106 of the
Amendments to the Massachusetts Constitution, provides:
"All people are born free and equal and have certain
natural, essential and unalienable rights; among which may be reckoned the right
of enjoying and defending their lives and liberties; that of acquiring,
possessing and protecting property; in fine, that of seeking and obtaining their
safety and happiness. Equality under the law shall not be denied or abridged
because of sex, race, color, creed or national origin."
This provision, even prior to its amendment, guaranteed to all
people in the Commonwealth -- equally -- the enjoyment of rights that are deemed
important or fundamental. The withholding of relief from the plaintiffs, who
wish to marry, and are otherwise eligible to marry, on the ground that the
couples are of the same gender, constitutes a categorical restriction of a
fundamental right. The restriction creates a straightforward case of
discrimination that disqualifies an entire group of our citizens and their
families from participation in an institution of paramount legal and social
importance. This is impermissible under art. 1.
Analysis begins with the indisputable premise that the
deprivation suffered by the plaintiffs is no mere legal inconvenience. The right
to marry is not a privilege conferred by the State, but a fundamental right that
is protected against unwarranted State interference. See Zablocki v. Redhail,
434 U.S. 374, 384 (1978) ("the right to marry is of fundamental importance
for all individuals"); Loving v. Virginia, 388 U.S. 1, 12 (1967) (freedom
to marry is "one of the vital personal rights essential to the orderly
pursuit of happiness by free men" under due process clause of Fourteenth
Amendment); Skinner v. Oklahoma, 316 U.S. 535, 541 (1942) (marriage is one of
"basic civil rights of man"). See also Turner v. Safley, 482 U.S. 78,
95-96 (1987) (prisoners' right to marry is constitutionally protected). This
right is essentially vitiated if one is denied the right to marry a person of
one's choice. See Zablocki v. Redhail, supra at 384 (all recent decisions of
United States Supreme Court place "the decision to marry as among the
personal decisions protected by the right of privacy").1[35]
Because our marriage statutes intend, and state, the ordinary
understanding that marriage under our law consists only of a union between a man
and a woman, they create a statutory classification based on the sex of the two
people who wish to marry. See Baehr v. Lewin, 74 Haw. 530, 564 (1993) (plurality
opinion) (Hawaii marriage statutes created sex-based classification); Baker v.
State, 170 Vt. 194, 253 (1999) (Johnson, J., concurring in part and dissenting
in part) (same). That the classification is sex based is self-evident. The
marriage statutes prohibit some applicants, such as the plaintiffs, from
obtaining a marriage license, and that prohibition is based solely on the
applicants' gender. As a factual matter, an individual's choice of marital
partner is constrained because of his or her own sex. Stated in particular
terms, Hillary Goodridge cannot marry Julie Goodridge because she (Hillary) is a
woman. Likewise, Gary Chalmers cannot marry Richard Linnell because he (Gary) is
a man. Only their gender prevents Hillary and Gary from marrying their chosen
partners under the present law.2[36]
A classification may be gender based whether or not the
challenged government action apportions benefits or burdens uniformly along
gender lines. This is so because constitutional protections extend to
individuals and not to categories of people. Thus, when an individual desires to
marry, but cannot marry his or her chosen partner because of the traditional
opposite-sex restriction, a violation of art. 1 has occurred. See Commonwealth
v. Chou, 433 Mass. 229, 237-238 (2001) (assuming statute enforceable only across
gender lines may offend Massachusetts equal rights amendment). I find it
disingenuous, at best, to suggest that such an individual's right to marry has
not been burdened at all, because he or she remains free to chose another
partner, who is of the opposite sex.
The equal protection infirmity at work here is strikingly
similar to (although, perhaps, more subtle than) the invidious discrimination
perpetuated by Virginia's antimiscegenation laws and unveiled in the decision of
Loving v. Virginia, supra. In its landmark decision striking down Virginia's ban
on marriages between Caucasians and members of any other race on both equal
protection and substantive due process grounds, the United States Supreme Court
soundly rejected the proposition that the equal application of the ban (i.e.,
that it applied equally to whites and blacks) made unnecessary the strict
scrutiny analysis traditionally required of statutes drawing classifications
according to race, see id. at 8-9, and concluded that "restricting the
freedom to marry solely because of racial classifications violates the central
meaning of the Equal Protection Clause." Id. at 12. That our marriage laws,
unlike antimiscegenation laws, were not enacted purposely to discriminate in no
way neutralizes their present discriminatory character.
With these two propositions established (the infringement on a fundamental right
and a sex-based classification), the enforcement of the marriage statutes as
they are currently understood is forbidden by our Constitution unless the State
can present a compelling purpose furthered by the statutes that can be
accomplished in no other reasonable manner.3[37]
See Blixt v. Blixt, 437 Mass. 649, 655-656 (2002), cert. denied, 537 U.S. 1189
(2003); Lowell v. Kowalski, 380 Mass. 663, 667-669 (1980). This the State has
not done. The justifications put forth by the State to sustain the statute's
exclusion of the plaintiffs are insufficient for the reasons explained by the
court, to which I add the following observations.
The rights of couples to have children, to adopt, and to be
foster parents, regardless of sexual orientation and marital status, are firmly
established. See E.N.O. v. L.M.M., 429 Mass. 824, 829, cert. denied, 528 U.S.
1005 (1999); Adoption of Tammy, 416 Mass. 205, 210-211 (1993). As recognized in
the court's opinion, and demonstrated by the record in this case, however, the
State's refusal to accord legal recognition to unions of same-sex couples has
had the effect of creating a system in which children of same-sex couples are
unable to partake of legal protections and social benefits taken for granted by
children in families whose parents are of the opposite sex. The continued
maintenance of this caste-like system is irreconcilable with, indeed, totally
repugnant to, the State's strong interest in the welfare of all children and its
primary focus, in the context of family law where children are concerned, on
"the best interests of the child." The issue at stake is not one, as
might ordinarily be the case, that can be unilaterally and totally deferred to
the wisdom of the Legislature. "While the State retains wide latitude to
decide the manner in which it will allocate benefits, it may not use criteria
which discriminatorily burden the exercise of a fundamental right." Moe v.
Secretary of Admin. & Fin., 382 Mass. 629, 652 (1981). Nor can the State's
wish to conserve resources be accomplished by invidious distinctions between
classes of citizens. See Plyler v. Doe, 457 U.S. 202, 216-217, 227 (1982).4[38]
A comment is in order with respect to the insistence of some
that marriage is, as a matter of definition, the legal union of a man and a
woman. To define the institution of marriage by the characteristics of those to
whom it always has been accessible, in order to justify the exclusion of those
to whom it never has been accessible, is conclusory and bypasses the core
question we are asked to decide.5[39]
This case calls for a higher level of legal analysis. Precisely, the case
requires that we confront ingrained assumptions with respect to historically
accepted roles of men and women within the institution of marriage and requires
that we reexamine these assumptions in light of the unequivocal language of art.
1, in order to ensure that the governmental conduct challenged here conforms to
the supreme charter of our Commonwealth. "A written constitution is the
fundamental law for the government of a sovereign State. It is the final
statement of the rights, privileges and obligations of the citizens and the
ultimate grant of the powers and the conclusive definition of the limitations of
the departments of State and of public officers . . . . To its
provisions the conduct of all governmental affairs must conform. From its terms
there is no appeal." Loring v. Young, 239 Mass. 349, 376-377 (1921). I do
not doubt the sincerity of deeply held moral or religious beliefs that make
inconceivable to some the notion that any change in the common-law definition of
what constitutes a legal civil marriage is now, or ever would be, warranted.
But, as matter of constitutional law, neither the mantra of tradition, nor
individual conviction, can justify the perpetuation of a hierarchy in which
couples of the same sex and their families are deemed less worthy of social and
legal recognition than couples of the opposite sex and their families. See
Lawrence v. Texas, 123 S. Ct. 2472, 2486 (2003) (O'Connor, J., concurring)
(moral disapproval, with no other valid State interest, cannot justify law that
discriminates against groups of persons); Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pa.
v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 850 (1992) ("Our obligation is to define the
liberty of all, not to mandate our own moral code").
(b) I am hopeful that our decision will be accepted by those
thoughtful citizens who believe that same-sex unions should not be approved by
the State. I am not referring here to acceptance in the sense of grudging
acknowledgment of the court's authority to adjudicate the matter. My hope is
more liberating. The plaintiffs are members of our community, our neighbors, our
coworkers, our friends. As pointed out by the court, their professions include
investment advisor, computer engineer, teacher, therapist, and lawyer. The
plaintiffs volunteer in our schools, worship beside us in our religious houses,
and have children who play with our children, to mention just a few ordinary
daily contacts. We share a common humanity and participate together in the
social contract that is the foundation of our Commonwealth. Simple principles of
decency dictate that we extend to the plaintiffs, and to their new status, full
acceptance, tolerance, and respect. We should do so because it is the right
thing to do. The union of two people contemplated by G. L. c. 207
"is a coming together for better or for worse, hopefully enduring, and
intimate to the degree of being sacred. It is an association that promotes a way
of life, not causes; a harmony in living, not political faiths; a bilateral
loyalty, not commercial or social projects. Yet it is an association for as
noble a purpose as any involved in our prior decisions." Griswold v.
Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479, 486 (1965). Because of the terms of art. 1, the
plaintiffs will no longer be excluded from that association.6[40]
SPINA, J. (dissenting, with whom Sosman and Cordy, JJ.,
join). What is at stake in this case is not the unequal treatment of individuals
or whether individual rights have been impermissibly burdened, but the power of
the Legislature to effectuate social change without interference from the
courts, pursuant to art. 30 of the Massachusetts Declaration of Rights.1[41]
The power to regulate marriage lies with the Legislature, not with the
judiciary. See Commonwealth v. Stowell , 389 Mass. 171, 175 (1983). Today, the
court has transformed its role as protector of individual rights into the role
of creator of rights, and I respectfully dissent.
1. Equal protection . Although the court did not address
the plaintiffs' gender discrimination claim, G. L. c. 207 does not
unconstitutionally discriminate on the basis of gender.2[42]
A claim of gender discrimination will lie where it is shown that differential
treatment disadvantages one sex over the other. See Attorney Gen . v.
Massachusetts Interscholastic Athletic Ass'n , 378 Mass. 342, 349-352 (1979).
See also United States v. Virginia , 518 U.S. 515 (1996). General Laws c. 207
enumerates certain qualifications for obtaining a marriage license. It creates
no distinction between the sexes, but applies to men and women in precisely the
same way. It does not create any disadvantage identified with gender, as both
men and women are similarly limited to marrying a person of the opposite sex.
See Commonwealth v. King , 374 Mass. 5, 15-22 (1977) (law prohibiting
prostitution not discriminatory based on gender because of equal application to
men and women).
Similarly, the marriage statutes do not discriminate on the basis of sexual
orientation. As the court correctly recognizes, constitutional protections are
extended to individuals, not couples. Ante n.15. The marriage statutes do not
disqualify individuals on the basis of sexual orientation from entering into
marriage. All individuals, with certain exceptions not relevant here, are free
to marry. Whether an individual chooses not to marry because of sexual
orientation or any other reason should be of no concern to the court.
The court concludes, however, that G. L. c. 207
unconstitutionally discriminates against the individual plaintiffs because it
denies them the “right to marry the person of one’s choice” where that
person is of the same sex. Ante at . To reach this result the court relies on
Loving v. Virginia , 388 U.S. 1, 12 (1967), and transforms “choice” into the
essential element of the institution of marriage. The Loving case did not use
the word “choice” in this manner, and it did not point to the result that
the court reaches today. In Loving , the Supreme Court struck down as
unconstitutional a statute that prohibited Caucasians from marrying
non-Caucasians. It concluded that the statute was intended to preserve white
supremacy and invidiously discriminated against non-Caucasians because of their
race. See id . at 11-12. The “choice” to which the Supreme Court referred
was the “choice to marry,” and it concluded that with respect to the
institution of marriage, the State had no compelling interest in limiting the
choice to marry along racial lines. Id . The Supreme Court did not imply the
existence of a right to marry a person of the same sex. To the same effect is
Perez v. Sharp , 32 Cal. 2d 711 (1948), on which the court also relies.
Unlike the Loving and Sharp cases, the Massachusetts
Legislature has erected no barrier to marriage that intentionally discriminates
against anyone. Within the institution of marriage,3[43]
anyone is free to marry, with certain exceptions that are not challenged. In the
absence of any discriminatory purpose, the State’s marriage statutes do not
violate principles of equal protection. See Washington v. Davis , 426 U.S. 229,
240 (1976) (“invidious quality of a law claimed to be . . . discriminatory
must ultimately be traced to a . . . discriminatory purpose”); Dickerson v.
Attorney Gen ., 396 Mass. 740, 743 (1986) (for purpose of equal protection
analysis, standard of review under State and Federal Constitutions is
identical). See also Attorney Gen . v. Massachusetts Interscholastic Athletic
Ass’n , supra . This court should not have invoked even the most deferential
standard of review within equal protection analysis because no individual was
denied access to the institution of marriage.
2. Due process . The marriage statutes do not impermissibly burden a right
protected by our constitutional guarantee of due process implicit in art. 10 of
our Declaration of Rights. There is no restriction on the right of any plaintiff
to enter into marriage. Each is free to marry a willing person of the opposite
sex. Cf. Zablocki v. Redhail , 434 U.S. 374 (1978) (fundamental right to marry
impermissibly burdened by statute requiring court approval when subject to child
support order).
Substantive due process protects individual rights against unwarranted
government intrusion. See Aime v. Commonwealth , 414 Mass. 667, 673 (1993). The
court states, as we have said on many occasions, that the Massachusetts
Declaration of Rights may protect a right in ways that exceed the protection
afforded by the Federal Constitution. Ante at . See Arizona v. Evans , 514 U.S.
1, 8 (1995) (State courts afforded broader protection of rights than granted by
United States Constitution). However, today the court does not fashion a remedy
that affords greater protection of a right. Instead, using the rubric of due
process, it has redefined marriage.
Although art. 10 may afford greater protection of rights
than the due process clause of the Fourteenth Amendment, our treatment of due
process challenges adheres to the same standards followed in Federal due process
analysis. See Commonwealth v. Ellis , 429 Mass. 362, 371 (1999). When analyzing
a claim that the State has impermissibly burdened an individual’s fundamental
or other right or liberty interest, “[w]e begin by sketching the contours of
the right asserted. We then inquire whether the challenged restriction burdens
that right.” Moe v. Secretary of Admin. & Fin ., 382 Mass. 629, 646
(1981). Where a right deemed “fundamental” is implicated, the challenged
restriction will be upheld only if it is “narrowly tailored to further a
legitimate and compelling governmental interest.” Aime v. Commonwealth , supra
at 673. To qualify as “fundamental” the asserted right must be
“objectively, ‘deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and tradition,’ [
Moore v. East Cleveland , 431 U.S. 494, 503 (1977) (plurality opinion)] . . .
and ‘implicit in the concept of ordered liberty,’ such that ‘neither
liberty nor justice would exist if they were sacrificed.’” Washington v.
Glucksberg , 521 U.S. 702, 720-721 (1997), quoting Palko v. Connecticut , 302
U.S. 319, 325, 326 (1937) (right to assisted suicide does not fall within
fundamental right to refuse medical treatment because novel and unsupported by
tradition) (citations omitted). See Three Juveniles v. Commonwealth , 390 Mass.
357, 367 (1983) (O’Connor, J., dissenting), cert. denied sub nom. Keefe v.
Massachusetts , 465 U.S. 1068 (1984). Rights that are not considered fundamental
merit due process protection if they have been irrationally burdened. See
Massachusetts Fed’n of Teachers v. Board of Educ ., 436 Mass. 763, 777-779
& n.14 (2002).
Although this court did not state that same-sex marriage is a fundamental right
worthy of strict scrutiny protection, it nonetheless deemed it a
constitutionally protected right by applying rational basis review. Before
applying any level of constitutional analysis there must be a recognized right
at stake. Same-sex marriage, or the “right to marry the person of one's
choice” as the court today defines that right, does not fall within the
fundamental right to marry. Same-sex marriage is not “deeply rooted in this
Nation’s history,” and the court does not suggest that it is. Except for the
occasional isolated decision in recent years, see, e.g., Baker v. State , 170
Vt. 194 (1999), same-sex marriage is not a right, fundamental or otherwise,
recognized in this country. Just one example of the Legislature's refusal to
recognize same-sex marriage can be found in a section of the legislation
amending G. L. c. 151B to prohibit discrimination in the workplace on the basis
of sexual orientation, which states: "Nothing in this act shall be
construed so as to legitimize or validate a ‘homosexual marriage’. . .
." St. 1989, c. 516, § 19. In this Commonwealth and in this country, the
roots of the institution of marriage are deeply set in history as a civil union
between a single man and a single woman. There is no basis for the court to
recognize same-sex marriage as a constitutionally protected right.
3. Remedy . The remedy that the court has fashioned both in
the name of equal protection and due process exceeds the bounds of judicial
restraint mandated by art. 30. The remedy that construes gender-specific
language as gender-neutral amounts to a statutory revision that replaces the
intent of the Legislature with that of the court. Article 30 permits the court
to apply principles of equal protection and to modify statutory language only if
legislative intent is preserved. See, e.g., Commonwealth v. Chou , 433 Mass.
229, 238-239 (2001) (judicial rewriting of gender language permissible only when
Legislature intended to include both men and women). See also Lowell v. Kowalski
, 380 Mass. 663, 670 (1980). Here, the alteration of the gender-specific
language alters precisely what the Legislature unambiguously intended to
preserve, the marital rights of single men and women. Such a dramatic change in
social institutions must remain at the behest of the people through the
democratic process.
Where the application of equal protection principles do not
permit rewriting a statute in a manner that preserves the intent of the
Legislature, we do not rewrite the statute. In Dalli v. Board of Educ ., 358
Mass. 753 (1971), the court refused to rewrite a statute in a manner that would
include unintended individuals. "To attempt to interpret this [statute] as
including those in the category of the plaintiff would be to engage in a
judicial enlargement of the clear statutory language beyond the limit of our
judicial function. We have traditionally and consistently declined to trespass
on legislative territory in deference to the time tested wisdom of the
separation of powers as expressed in art. [30] of the Declaration of Rights of
the Constitution of Massachusetts even when it appeared that a highly desirable
and just result might thus be achieved." Id . at 759. Recently, in Connors
v. Boston , 430 Mass. 31 (1999), we refused to expand health insurance coverage
to include domestic partners because such an expansion was within the province
of the Legislature, where policy affecting family relationships is most
appropriate and frequently considered. Id . at 42-43. Principles of equal
protection do not permit the marriage statutes to be changed in the manner that
we have seen today.
This court has previously exercised the judicial restraint
mandated by art. 30 and declined to extend due process protection to rights not
traditionally coveted, despite recognition of their social importance. See
Tobin's Case , 424 Mass. 250, 252-253 (1997) (receiving workers’ compensation
benefits not fundamental right); Doe v. Superintendent of Schs. of Worcester ,
421 Mass. 117, 129 (1995) (declaring education not fundamental right); Williams
v. Secretary of the Executive Office of Human Servs ., 414 Mass. 551, 565 (1993)
(no fundamental right to receive mental health services); Matter of Tocci , 413
Mass. 542, 548 n.4 (1992) (no fundamental right to practice law); Commonwealth
v. Henry's Drywall Co ., 366 Mass. 539, 542 (1974) (no fundamental right to
pursue one's business). Courts have authority to recognize rights that are
supported by the Constitution and history, but the power to create novel rights
is reserved for the people through the democratic and legislative processes.
Likewise, the Supreme Court exercises restraint in the application of
substantive due process “‘because guideposts for responsible decisionmaking
in this unchartered area are scarce and open-ended.’ [ Collins v. Harker
Heights , 503 U.S. 115, 125 (1992).] By extending constitutional protection to
an asserted right or liberty interest, we, to a great extent, place the matter
outside the arena of public debate and legislative action. We must therefore
‘exercise the utmost care whenever we are asked to break new ground in this
field,’ [ id .], lest the liberty protected by the Due Process Clause be
subtly transformed into the policy preferences of the Members of this Court,
Moore [v. East Cleveland , 431 U.S. 494, 502 (1977)] (plurality opinion).”
Washington v. Glucksberg , supra at 720.
The court has extruded a new right from principles of
substantive due process, and in doing so it has distorted the meaning and
purpose of due process. The purpose of substantive due process is to protect
existing rights, not to create new rights. Its aim is to thwart government
intrusion, not invite it. The court asserts that the Massachusetts Declaration
of Rights serves to guard against government intrusion into each individual's
sphere of privacy. Ante at . Similarly, the Supreme Court has called for
increased due process protection when individual privacy and intimacy are
threatened by unnecessary government imposition. See, e.g., Lawrence v. Texas ,
123 S. Ct. 2472 (2003) (private nature of sexual behavior implicates increased
due process protection); Eisenstadt v. Baird , 405 U.S. 438 (1972) (privacy
protection extended to procreation decisions within nonmarital context);
Griswold v. Connecticut , 381 U.S. 479 (1965) (due process invoked because of
intimate nature of procreation decisions). These cases, along with the Moe case,
focus on the threat to privacy when government seeks to regulate the most
intimate activity behind bedroom doors. The statute in question does not seek to
regulate intimate activity within an intimate relationship, but merely gives
formal recognition to a particular marriage. The State has respected the private
lives of the plaintiffs, and has done nothing to intrude in the relationships
that each of the plaintiff couples enjoy. Cf. Lawrence v. Texas , supra at 2484
(case "does not involve whether the government must give formal recognition
to any relationship that homosexual persons seek to enter"). Ironically, by
extending the marriage laws to same-sex couples the court has turned substantive
due process on its head and used it to interject government into the
plaintiffs’ lives.
SOSMAN, J. (dissenting, with whom Spina and Cordy, JJ., join).
In applying the rational basis test to any challenged statutory scheme, the
issue is not whether the Legislature's rationale behind that scheme is
persuasive to us, but only whether it satisfies a minimal threshold of
rationality. Today, rather than apply that test, the court announces that,
because it is persuaded that there are no differences between same-sex and
opposite-sex couples, the Legislature has no rational basis for treating them
differently with respect to the granting of marriage licenses.1[44]
Reduced to its essence, the court's opinion concludes that, because same-sex
couples are now raising children, and withholding the benefits of civil marriage
from their union makes it harder for them to raise those children, the State
must therefore provide the benefits of civil marriage to same-sex couples just
as it does to opposite-sex couples. Of course, many people are raising children
outside the confines of traditional marriage, and, by definition, those children
are being deprived of the various benefits that would flow if they were being
raised in a household with married parents. That does not mean that the
Legislature must accord the full benefits of marital status on every household
raising children. Rather, the Legislature need only have some rational basis for
concluding that, at present, those alternate family structures have not yet been
conclusively shown to be the equivalent of the marital family structure that has
established itself as a successful one over a period of centuries. People are of
course at liberty to raise their children in various family structures, as long
as they are not literally harming their children by doing so. See Blixt v.
Blixt, 437 Mass. 649, 668-670 (2002) (Sosman, J., dissenting), cert. denied, 537
U.S. 1189 (2003). That does not mean that the State is required to provide
identical forms of encouragement, endorsement, and support to all of the
infinite variety of household structures that a free society permits.
Based on our own philosophy of child rearing, and on our
observations of the children being raised by same-sex couples to whom we are
personally close, we may be of the view that what matters to children is not the
gender, or sexual orientation, or even the number of the adults who raise them,
but rather whether those adults provide the children with a nurturing, stable,
safe, consistent, and supportive environment in which to mature. Same-sex
couples can provide their children with the requisite nurturing, stable, safe,
consistent, and supportive environment in which to mature, just as opposite-sex
couples do. It is therefore understandable that the court might view the
traditional definition of marriage as an unnecessary anachronism, rooted in
historical prejudices that modern society has in large measure rejected and
biological limitations that modern science has overcome.
It is not, however, our assessment that matters. Conspicuously
absent from the court's opinion today is any acknowledgment that the attempts at
scientific study of the ramifications of raising children in same-sex couple
households are themselves in their infancy and have so far produced inconclusive
and conflicting results. Notwithstanding our belief that gender and sexual
orientation of parents should not matter to the success of the child rearing
venture, studies to date reveal that there are still some observable differences
between children raised by opposite-sex couples and children raised by same-sex
couples. See post at - (Cordy, J., dissenting). Interpretation of the data
gathered by those studies then becomes clouded by the personal and political
beliefs of the investigators, both as to whether the differences identified are
positive or negative, and as to the untested explanations of what might account
for those differences. (This is hardly the first time in history that the
ostensible steel of the scientific method has melted and buckled under the
intense heat of political and religious passions.) Even in the absence of bias
or political agenda behind the various studies of children raised by same-sex
couples, the most neutral and strict application of scientific principles to
this field would be constrained by the limited period of observation that has
been available. Gay and lesbian couples living together openly, and official
recognition of them as their children's sole parents, comprise a very recent
phenomenon, and the recency of that phenomenon has not yet permitted any study
of how those children fare as adults and at best minimal study of how they fare
during their adolescent years. The Legislature can rationally view the state of
the scientific evidence as unsettled on the critical question it now faces: Are
families headed by same-sex parents equally successful in rearing children from
infancy to adulthood as families headed by parents of opposite sexes? Our belief
that children raised by same-sex couples should fare the same as children raised
in traditional families is just that: a passionately held but utterly untested
belief. The Legislature is not required to share that belief but may, as the
creator of the institution of civil marriage, wish to see the proof before
making a fundamental alteration to that institution.
Although ostensibly applying the rational basis test to the
civil marriage statutes, it is abundantly apparent that the court is in fact
applying some undefined stricter standard to assess the constitutionality of the
marriage statutes' exclusion of same-sex couples. While avoiding any express
conclusion as to any of the proffered routes by which that exclusion would be
subjected to a test of strict scrutiny -- infringement of a fundamental right,
discrimination based on gender, or discrimination against gays and lesbians as a
suspect classification -- the opinion repeatedly alludes to those concepts in a
prolonged and eloquent prelude before articulating its view that the exclusion
lacks even a rational basis. See, e.g., ante at (noting that State Constitution
is "more protective of individual liberty and equality," demands
"broader protection for fundamental rights," and is "less
tolerant of government intrusion into the protected spheres of private
life" than Federal Constitution); ante at (describing decision to marry and
choice of marital partner as "among life's momentous acts of
self-definition"); ante at - (repeated references to "right to
marry" as "fundamental"); ante at - (repeated comparisons to
statutes prohibiting interracial marriage, which were predicated on suspect
classification of race); ante at - (characterizing ban on same-sex marriage as
"invidious" discrimination that "deprives individuals of access
to an institution of fundamental legal, personal, and social significance"
and again noting that Massachusetts Constitution "protects matters of
personal liberty against government incursion" more zealously than Federal
Constitution); ante at (characterizing "whom to marry, how to express
sexual intimacy, and whether and how to establish a family" as "among
the most basic of every individual's liberty and due process rights"); id.
("liberty interest in choosing whether and whom to marry would be
hollow" if Commonwealth could "foreclose an individual from freely
choosing the person" to marry); ante at (opining that in "overlapping
realms of personal autonomy, marriage, family life, and child rearing,"
characterized as "fundamentally private areas of life," court uses
"integrated" analysis instead of "narrow focus"). See also
ante at n.29 (suggesting that prohibition on same-sex marriage "impose[s]
limits on personal beliefs"); ante at n.31 (suggesting that "total
deference" to Legislature in this case would be equivalent to
"strip[ping]" judiciary "of its constitutional authority to
decide challenges" in such areas as forced sterilization, antimiscegenation
statutes, and abortion, even though all cited examples pertain to fundamental
rights analyzed under strict scrutiny, not under rational basis test); ante at
(civil marriage as "a right of fundamental importance"); ante at
(noting State policy of "preventing discrimination on the basis of sexual
orientation"); id. (prohibition against same-sex marriage inconsistent with
"gender-neutral laws promoting stable families," and "rooted in
persistent prejudices against" homosexuals); ante at (prohibition against
same-sex marriage "violated the basic premises of individual
liberty"). In short, while claiming to apply a mere rational basis test,
the court's opinion works up an enormous head of steam by repeated invocations
of avenues by which to subject the statute to strict scrutiny, apparently hoping
that that head of steam will generate momentum sufficient to propel the opinion
across the yawning chasm of the very deferential rational basis test.
Shorn of these emotion-laden invocations, the opinion
ultimately opines that the Legislature is acting irrationally when it grants
benefits to a proven successful family structure while denying the same benefits
to a recent, perhaps promising, but essentially untested alternate family
structure. Placed in a more neutral context, the court would never find any
irrationality in such an approach. For example, if the issue were government
subsidies and tax benefits promoting use of an established technology for energy
efficient heating, the court would find no equal protection or due process
violation in the Legislature's decision not to grant the same benefits to an
inventor or manufacturer of some new, alternative technology who did not yet
have sufficient data to prove that that new technology was just as good as the
established technology. That the early results from preliminary testing of the
new technology might look very promising, or that the theoretical underpinnings
of the new technology might appear flawless, would not make it irrational for
the Legislature to grant subsidies and tax breaks to the established technology
and deny them to the still unproved newcomer in the field. While programs that
affect families and children register higher on our emotional scale than
programs affecting energy efficiency, our standards for what is or is not
"rational" should not be bent by those emotional tugs. Where, as here,
there is no ground for applying strict scrutiny, the emotionally compelling
nature of the subject matter should not affect the manner in which we apply the
rational basis test.
Or, to the extent that the court is going to invoke such
emotion-laden and value-laden rhetoric as a means of heightening the degree of
scrutiny to be applied, the same form of rhetoric can be employed to justify the
Legislature's proceeding with extreme caution in this area. In considering
whether the Legislature has a rational reason for postponing a dramatic change
to the definition of marriage, it is surely pertinent to the inquiry to
recognize that this proffered change affects not just a load-bearing wall of our
social structure but the very cornerstone of that structure. See post at -
(Cordy, J., dissenting). Before making a fundamental alteration to that
cornerstone, it is eminently rational for the Legislature to require a high
degree of certainty as to the precise consequences of that alteration, to make
sure that it can be done safely, without either temporary or lasting damage to
the structural integrity of the entire edifice. The court today blithely assumes
that there are no such dangers and that it is safe to proceed (see ante at - ,
an assumption that is not supported by anything more than the court's blind
faith that it is so.
More importantly, it is not our confidence in the lack of
adverse consequences that is at issue, or even whether that confidence is
justifiable. The issue is whether it is rational to reserve judgment on whether
this change can be made at this time without damaging the institution of
marriage or adversely affecting the critical role it has played in our society.
Absent consensus on the issue (which obviously does not exist), or unanimity
amongst scientists studying the issue (which also does not exist), or a more
prolonged period of observation of this new family structure (which has not yet
been possible), it is rational for the Legislature to postpone any redefinition
of marriage that would include same-sex couples until such time as it is certain
that that redefinition will not have unintended and undesirable social
consequences. Through the political process, the people may decide when the
benefits of extending civil marriage to same-sex couples have been shown to
outweigh whatever risks -- be they palpable or ephemeral -- are involved.
However minimal the risks of that redefinition of marriage may seem to us from
our vantage point, it is not up to us to decide what risks society must run, and
it is inappropriate for us to arrogate that power to ourselves merely because we
are confident that "it is the right thing to do." Ante at (Greaney,
J., concurring).
As a matter of social history, today's opinion may represent a
great turning point that many will hail as a tremendous step toward a more just
society. As a matter of constitutional jurisprudence, however, the case stands
as an aberration. To reach the result it does, the court has tortured the
rational basis test beyond recognition. I fully appreciate the strength of the
temptation to find this particular law unconstitutional – there is much to be
said for the argument that excluding gay and lesbian couples from the benefits
of civil marriage is cruelly unfair and hopelessly outdated; the inability to
marry has a profound impact on the personal lives of committed gay and lesbian
couples (and their children) to whom we are personally close (our friends,
neighbors, family members, classmates, and co-workers); and our resolution of
this issue takes place under the intense glare of national and international
publicity. Speaking metaphorically, these factors have combined to turn the case
before us into a "perfect storm" of a constitutional question. In my
view, however, such factors make it all the more imperative that we adhere
precisely and scrupulously to the established guideposts of our constitutional
jurisprudence, a jurisprudence that makes the rational basis test an extremely
deferential one that focuses on the rationality, not the persuasiveness, of the
potential justifications for the classifications in the legislative scheme. I
trust that, once this particular "storm" clears, we will return to the
rational basis test as it has always been understood and applied. Applying that
deferential test in the manner it is customarily applied, the exclusion of gay
and lesbian couples from the institution of civil marriage passes constitutional
muster. I respectfully dissent.
CORDY, J. (dissenting, with whom Spina and Sosman, JJ., join).
The court's opinion concludes that the Department of Public Health has failed to
identify any "constitutionally adequate reason" for limiting civil
marriage to opposite-sex unions, and that there is no "reasonable
relationship" between a disqualification of same-sex couples who wish to
enter into a civil marriage and the protection of public health, safety, or
general welfare. Consequently, it holds that the marriage statute cannot
withstand scrutiny under the Massachusetts Constitution. Because I find these
conclusions to be unsupportable in light of the nature of the rights and
regulations at issue, the presumption of constitutional validity and significant
deference afforded to legislative enactments, and the "undesirability of
the judiciary substituting its notions of correct policy for that of a popularly
elected Legislature" responsible for making such policy, Zayre Corp. v.
Attorney Gen., 372 Mass. 423, 433 (1977), I respectfully dissent. Although it
may be desirable for many reasons to extend to same-sex couples the benefits and
burdens of civil marriage (and the plaintiffs have made a powerfully reasoned
case for that extension), that decision must be made by the Legislature, not the
court.
If a statute either impairs the exercise of a fundamental
right protected by the due process or liberty provisions of our State
Constitution, or discriminates based on a constitutionally suspect
classification such as sex, it will be subject to strict scrutiny when its
validity is challenged. See Blixt v. Blixt, 437 Mass. 649, 655-656, 660-661
(2002), cert. denied, 537 U.S. 1189 (2003) (fundamental right); Lowell v.
Kowalski, 380 Mass. 663, 666 (1980) (sex-based classification). If it does
neither, a statute "will be upheld if it is 'rationally related to a
legitimate State purpose.'" Hallett v. Wrentham, 398 Mass. 550, 557 (1986),
quoting Paro v. Longwood Hosp., 373 Mass. 645, 649 (1977). This test, referred
to in State and Federal constitutional jurisprudence as the "rational basis
test,"1[45] is virtually
identical in substance and effect to the test applied to a law promulgated under
the State's broad police powers (pursuant to which the marriage statutes and
most other licensing and regulatory laws are enacted): that is, the law is valid
if it is reasonably related to the protection of public health, safety, or
general welfare. See, e.g., Leigh v. Board of Registration in Nursing, 395 Mass.
670, 682-683 (1985) (applying rational basis review to question of State
exercise of police power).
The Massachusetts marriage statute does not impair the
exercise of a recognized fundamental right, or discriminate on the basis of sex
in violation of the equal rights amendment to the Massachusetts Constitution.
Consequently, it is subject to review only to determine whether it satisfies the
rational basis test. Because a conceivable rational basis exists upon which the
Legislature could conclude that the marriage statute furthers the legitimate
State purpose of ensuring, promoting, and supporting an optimal social structure
for the bearing and raising of children, it is a valid exercise of the State's
police power.
A. Limiting marriage to the union of one man and one woman does not impair the
exercise of a fundamental right. Civil marriage is an institution created by the
State. In Massachusetts, the marriage statutes are derived from English common
law, see Commonwealth v. Knowlton, 2 Mass. 530, 534 (1807), and were first
enacted in colonial times. Commonwealth v. Munson, 127 Mass. 459, 460 (1879).
They were enacted to secure public interests and not for religious purposes or
to promote personal interests or aspirations. (See discussion infra at - ). As
the court notes in its opinion, the institution of marriage is "the legal
union of a man and woman as husband and wife," ante at , and it has always
been so under Massachusetts law, colonial or otherwise.
The plaintiffs contend that because the right to choose to
marry is a "fundamental" right, the right to marry the person of one's
choice, including a member of the same sex, must also be a
"fundamental" right. While the court stops short of deciding that the
right to marry someone of the same sex is "fundamental" such that
strict scrutiny must be applied to any statute that impairs it, it nevertheless
agrees with the plaintiffs that the right to choose to marry is of fundamental
importance ("among the most basic" of every person's "liberty and
due process rights") and would be "hollow" if an individual was
foreclosed from "freely choosing the person with whom to share . . . the .
. . institution of civil marriage." Ante at . Hence, it concludes that a
marriage license cannot be denied to an individual who wishes to marry someone
of the same sex. In reaching this result the court has transmuted the
"right" to marry into a right to change the institution of marriage
itself. This feat of reasoning succeeds only if one accepts the proposition that
the definition of the institution of marriage as a union between a man and a
woman is merely "conclusory" (as suggested, ante at [Greaney, J.,
concurring]), rather than the basis on which the "right" to partake in
it has been deemed to be of fundamental importance. In other words, only by
assuming that "marriage" includes the union of two persons of the same
sex does the court conclude that restricting marriage to opposite-sex couples
infringes on the "right" of same-sex couples to "marry."2[46]
The plaintiffs ground their contention that they have a
fundamental right to marry a person of the same sex in a long line of Supreme
Court decisions, e.g., Turner v. Safley, 482 U.S. 78 (1987); Zablocki v.
Redhail, 434 U.S. 374 (1978); Loving v. Virginia, 388 U.S. 1 (1967); Griswold v.
Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479 (1965); Skinner v. Oklahoma, 316 U.S. 535 (1942); that
discuss the importance of marriage. In context, all of these decisions and their
discussions are about the "fundamental" nature of the institution of
marriage as it has existed and been understood in this country, not as the court
has redefined it today. Even in that context, its "fundamental" nature
is derivative of the nature of the interests that underlie or are associated
with it.3[47] An examination of
those interests reveals that they are either not shared by same-sex couples or
not implicated by the marriage statutes.
Supreme Court cases that have described marriage or the right
to marry as "fundamental" have focused primarily on the underlying
interest of every individual in procreation, which, historically, could only
legally occur within the construct of marriage because sexual intercourse
outside of marriage was a criminal act.4[48]
In Skinner v. Oklahoma, supra, the first case to characterize marriage as a
"fundamental" right, the Supreme Court stated, as its rationale for
striking down a sterilization statute, that "[m]arriage and procreation are
fundamental to the very existence of the race." Id. at 541. In concluding
that a sterilized individual "is forever deprived of a basic liberty,"
id., the Court was obviously referring to procreation rather than marriage, as
this court recognized in Matter of Moe, 385 Mass. 555, 560 (1982). Similarly, in
Loving v. Virginia, supra, in which the United States Supreme Court struck down
Virginia's antimiscegenation statute, the Court implicitly linked marriage with
procreation in describing marriage as "fundamental to our very
existence." Id. at 12. In Zablocki v. Redhail, supra, the Court expressly
linked the right to marry with the right to procreate, concluding that "if
[the plaintiff's] right to procreate means anything at all, it must imply some
right to enter the only relationship in which the State . . . allows sexual
relations legally to take place." Id. at 386. Once again, in Turner v.
Safley, supra, striking a State regulation that curtailed the right of an inmate
to marry, the Court included among the important attributes of such marriages
the "expectation that [the marriage] ultimately will be fully
consummated." Id. at 96. See Milford v. Worcester, 7 Mass. 48, 52 (1810)
(purpose of marriage is "to regulate, chasten, and refine, the intercourse
between the sexes; and to multiply [and] preserve . . . the species").
Because same-sex couples are unable to procreate on their own, any right to
marriage they may possess cannot be based on their interest in procreation,
which has been essential to the Supreme Court's denomination of the right to
marry as fundamental.
Supreme Court cases recognizing a right to privacy in intimate decision-making,
e.g., Griswold v. Connecticut, supra (striking down statute prohibiting use of
contraceptives); Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113 (1973) (striking down statute
criminalizing abortion), have also focused primarily on sexual relations and the
decision whether or not to procreate, and have refused to recognize an
"unlimited right" to privacy. Id. at 154. Massachusetts courts have
been no more willing than the Federal courts to adopt a "universal[]"
"privacy doctrine," Marcoux v. Attorney Gen., 375 Mass. 63, 67 (1978),
or to derive "controversial 'new' rights from the Constitution." Aime
v. Commonwealth, 414 Mass. 667, 674 n.10 (1993).
What the Griswold Court found "repulsive to the notions
of privacy surrounding the marriage relationship" was the prospect of
"allow[ing] the police to search the sacred precincts of marital bedrooms
for telltale signs of the use of contraceptives." Griswold v. Connecticut,
supra at 485-486. See Moe v. Secretary of Admin. & Fin., 382 Mass. 629, 658
(1981), quoting L. Tribe, American Constitutional Law 924 (1978) (finding it
"difficult to imagine a clearer case of bodily intrusion" than being
forced to bear a child). When Justice Goldberg spoke of "marital
relations" in the context of finding it "difficult to imagine what is
more private or more intimate than a husband and wife's marital
relations[hip]," Griswold v. Connecticut, supra at 495 (Goldberg, J.,
concurring), he was obviously referring to sexual relations.5[49]
Similarly, in Lawrence v. Texas, 123 S. Ct. 2472 (2003), it was the
criminalization of private sexual behavior that the Court found violative of the
petitioners' liberty interest.
In Massachusetts jurisprudence, protected decisions generally
have been limited to those concerning "whether or not to beget or bear a
child," Matter of Moe, 385 Mass. 555, 564 (1982) (see Opinion of the
Justices, 423 Mass. 1201, 1234-1235 [1996] ["focus of (the Griswold and Roe
cases) and the cases following them has been the intrusion . . . into the
especially intimate aspects of a person's life implicated in procreation and
childbearing"]); how to raise a child, see Care & Protection of Robert,
408 Mass. 52, 58, 60 (1990); or whether or not to accept medical treatment, see
Brophy v. New England Sinai Hosp., Inc., 398 Mass. 417, 430 (1986);
Superintendent of Belchertown State Sch. v. Saikewicz, 373 Mass. 728, 742
(1977), none of which is at issue here. See also Commonwealth v. Balthazar, 366
Mass. 298, 301 (1974) (statute punishing unnatural and lascivious acts does not
apply to sexual conduct engaged in by adults in private, in light of
"articulation of the constitutional right of an individual to be free from
government regulation of certain sex related activities").
The marriage statute, which regulates only the act of obtaining a marriage
license, does not implicate privacy in the sense that it has found
constitutional protection under Massachusetts and Federal law. Cf. Commonwealth
v. King, 374 Mass. 5, 14 (1977) (solicitation of prostitution "while in a
place to which the public had access" implicated no "constitutionally
protected rights of privacy"); Marcoux v. Attorney Gen., supra at 68 (right
to privacy, at most, protects conduct "limited more or less to the
hearth"). It does not intrude on any right that the plaintiffs have to
privacy in their choices regarding procreation, an intimate partner or sexual
relations.6[50] The plaintiffs'
right to privacy in such matters does not require that the State officially
endorse their choices in order for the right to be constitutionally vindicated.
Although some of the privacy cases also speak in terms of
personal autonomy, no court has ever recognized such an open-ended right.
"That many of the rights and liberties protected by the Due Process Clause
sound in personal autonomy does not warrant the sweeping conclusion that any and
all important, intimate, and personal decisions are so protected . . . ."
Washington v. Glucksberg, 521 U.S. 702, 727 (1997). Such decisions are protected
not because they are important, intimate, and personal, but because the right or
liberty at stake is "so deeply rooted in our history and traditions, or so
fundamental to our concept of constitutionally ordered liberty" that it is
protected by due process. Id. Accordingly, the Supreme Court has concluded that
while the decision to refuse unwanted medical treatment is fundamental, Cruzan
v. Director, Mo. Dep't of Health, 497 U.S. 261, 278 (1990), because it is deeply
rooted in our nation's history and tradition, the equally personal and profound
decision to commit suicide is not because of the absence of such roots.
Washington v. Glucksberg, supra.
While the institution of marriage is deeply rooted in the history and traditions
of our country and our State, the right to marry someone of the same sex is not.
No matter how personal or intimate a decision to marry someone of the same sex
might be, the right to make it is not guaranteed by the right of personal
autonomy.
The protected right to freedom of association, in the sense of
freedom of choice "to enter into and maintain certain intimate human
relationships," Roberts v. United States Jaycees, 468 U.S. 609, 617 (1984)
(as an element of liberty or due process rather than free speech), is similarly
limited and unimpaired by the marriage statute. As recognized by the Supreme
Court, that right affords protection only to "certain kinds of highly
personal relationships," id. at 618, such as those between husband and
wife, parent and child, and among close relatives, id. at 619, that "have
played a critical role in the culture and traditions of the Nation," id. at
618-619, and are "deeply rooted in this Nation's history and
tradition." Moore v. East Cleveland, 431 U.S. 494, 498-499, 503 (1977)
(distinguishing on this basis between family and nonfamily relationships).
Unlike opposite-sex marriages, which have deep historic roots, or the
parent-child relationship, which reflects a "strong tradition" founded
on "the history and culture of Western civilization" and "is now
established beyond debate as an enduring American tradition," Wisconsin v.
Yoder, 406 U.S. 205, 232 (1972); or extended family relationships, which have
been "honored throughout our history," Moore v. East Cleveland, supra
at 505, same-sex relationships, although becoming more accepted, are certainly
not so "deeply rooted in this Nation's history and tradition" as to
warrant such enhanced constitutional protection.
Although "expressions of emotional support and public
commitment" have been recognized as among the attributes of marriage,
which, "[t]aken together . . . form a constitutionally protected marital
relationship" (emphasis added), Turner v. Safley, 482 U.S. 78, 95, 96
(1987), those interests, standing alone, are not the source of a fundamental
right to marry. While damage to one's "status in the community" may be
sufficient harm to confer standing to sue, Lowell v. Kowalski, 380 Mass. 663,
667 (1980), such status has never been recognized as a fundamental right. See
Paul v. Davis, 424 U.S. 693, 701 (1976) (mere damage to reputation does not
constitute deprivation of "liberty").
Finally, the constitutionally protected interest in child rearing, recognized in
Meyer v. Nebraska, 262 U.S. 390, 399 (1923); Pierce v. Society of Sisters, 268
U.S. 510, 534-535 (1925); and Care & Protection of Robert, supra at 58, 60,
is not implicated or infringed by the marriage statute here. The fact that the
plaintiffs cannot marry has no bearing on their independently protected
constitutional rights as parents which, as with opposite-sex parents, are
limited only by their continued fitness and the best interests of their
children. Bezio v. Patenaude, 381 Mass. 563, 579 (1980) (courts may not use
parent's sexual orientation as reason to deny child custody).
Because the rights and interests discussed above do not afford the plaintiffs
any fundamental right that would be impaired by a statute limiting marriage to
members of the opposite sex, they have no fundamental right to be declared
"married" by the State.
Insofar as the right to marry someone of the same sex is
neither found in the unique historical context of our Constitution7[51]
nor compelled by the meaning ascribed by this court to the liberty and due
process protections contained within it, should the court nevertheless recognize
it as a fundamental right? The consequences of deeming a right to be
"fundamental" are profound, and this court, as well as the Supreme
Court, has been very cautious in recognizing them.8[52]
Such caution is required by separation of powers principles. If a right is found
to be "fundamental," it is, to a great extent, removed from "the
arena of public debate and legislative action"; utmost care must be taken
when breaking new ground in this field "lest the liberty protected by the
Due Process Clause be subtly transformed into the policy preferences of
[judges]." Washington v. Glucksberg, 521 U.S. 702, 720 (1997).
"[T]o rein in" the otherwise potentially unlimited scope of
substantive due process rights, id. at 722, both Federal and Massachusetts
courts have recognized as "fundamental" only those "rights and
liberties which are, objectively, 'deeply rooted in this Nation's history and
tradition,' [Moore v. East Cleveland, supra at 503] . . . and 'implicit in the
concept of ordered liberty.'" Id. at 720-721, quoting Palko v. Connecticut,
302 U.S. 319, 325 (1937). See Dutil, petitioner, 437 Mass. 9, 13 (2002) (same).
In the area of family-related rights in particular, the Supreme Court has
emphasized that the "Constitution protects the sanctity of the family
precisely because the institution of the family is deeply rooted." Moore v.
East Cleveland, supra.9[53]
Applying this limiting principle, the Supreme Court, as noted
above, declined to recognize a fundamental right to physician-assisted suicide,
which would have required "revers[ing] centuries of legal doctrine and
practice, and strik[ing] down the considered policy choice of almost every
State." Washington v. Glucksberg, supra at 723. While recognizing that
public attitudes toward assisted suicide are currently the subject of
"earnest and profound debate," the Court nevertheless left the
continuation and resolution of that debate to the political arena, "as it
should be in a democratic society." Id. at 719, 735.
Similarly, Massachusetts courts have declined to recognize
rights that are not so deeply rooted.10[54]
As this court noted in considering whether to recognize a right of terminally
ill patients to refuse life-prolonging treatment, "the law always lags
behind the most advanced thinking in every area," and must await "some
common ground, some consensus." Superintendent of Belchertown State Sch. v.
Saikewicz, 373 Mass. 728, 737 (1977), quoting Burger, The Law and Medical
Advances, 67 Annals Internal Med. Supp. 7, 15, 17 (1967). See Blixt v. Blixt,
437 Mass. 649, 662-663 n.22 (2002) ("social consensus about family
relationships is relevant to the constitutional limits on State
intervention").
This is not to say that a statute that has no rational basis must nevertheless
be upheld as long as it is of ancient origin. However, "[t]he long history
of a certain practice . . . and its acceptance as an uncontroversial part of our
national and State tradition do suggest that [the court] should reflect
carefully before striking it down." Colo v. Treasurer & Receiver Gen.,
378 Mass. 550, 557 (1979). As this court has recognized, the "fact that a
challenged practice 'is followed by a large number of states . . . is plainly
worth considering in determining whether the practice "offends some
principle of justice so rooted in the traditions and conscience of our people as
to be ranked as fundamental."'" Commonwealth v. Kostka, 370 Mass. 516,
533 (1976), quoting Leland v. Oregon, 343 U.S. 790, 798 (1952).
Although public attitudes toward marriage in general and
same-sex marriage in particular have changed and are still evolving, "the
asserted contemporary concept of marriage and societal interests for which
[plaintiffs] contend" are "manifestly [less] deeply founded" than
the "historic institution" of marriage. Matter of the Estate of
Cooper, 187 A.D.2d 128, 133-134 (N.Y. 1993). Indeed, it is not readily apparent
to what extent contemporary values have embraced the concept of same-sex
marriage. Perhaps the "clearest and most reliable objective evidence of
contemporary values is the legislation enacted by the country's
legislatures," Atkins v. Virginia, 536 U.S. 304, 312 (2002), quoting Penry
v. Lynaugh, 492 U.S. 302, 331 (1989). No State Legislature has enacted laws
permitting same-sex marriages; and a large majority of States, as well as the
United States Congress, have affirmatively prohibited the recognition of such
marriages for any purpose. See P. Greenberg, State Laws Affecting Lesbians and
Gays, National Conference of State Legislatures Legisbriefs at 1 (April/May
2001) (reporting that, as of May, 2001, thirty-six States had enacted
"defense of marriage" statutes); 1 U.S.C. § 7 (2000); 28 U.S.C.
§ 1738C (2000) (Federal Defense of Marriage Act).
Given this history and the current state of public opinion, as
reflected in the actions of the people's elected representatives, it cannot be
said that "a right to same-sex marriage is so rooted in the traditions and
collective conscience of our people that failure to recognize it would violate
the fundamental principles of liberty and justice that lie at the base of all
our civil and political institutions. Neither . . . [is] a right to same-sex
marriage . . . implicit in the concept of ordered liberty, such that neither
liberty nor justice would exist if it were sacrificed." Baehr v. Lewin, 74
Haw. 530, 556-557 (1993). See Dean v. District of Columbia, 653 A.2d 307, 333
(D.C. 1995) (per curiam) (Ferren, J., concurring in part and dissenting in
part); Baker v. Nelson, 291 Minn. 310, 312 (1971), appeal dismissed, 409 U.S.
810 (1972); Storrs v. Holcomb, 168 Misc. 2d 898, 899-900 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. 1996),
dismissed, 245 A.D.2d 943 (N.Y. 1997).11[55]
In such circumstances, the law with respect to same-sex marriages must be left
to develop through legislative processes, subject to the constraints of
rationality, lest the court be viewed as using the liberty and due process
clauses as vehicles merely to enforce its own views regarding better social
policies, a role that the strongly worded separation of powers principles in
art. 30 of the Declaration of Rights of our Constitution forbids, and for which
the court is particularly ill suited.
B. The marriage statute, in limiting marriage to heterosexual
couples, does not constitute discrimination on the basis of sex in violation of
the Equal Rights Amendment to the Massachusetts Constitution. In his
concurrence, Justice Greaney contends that the marriage statute constitutes
discrimination on the basis of sex in violation of art. 1 of the Declaration of
Rights as amended by art. 106 of the Amendments to the Constitution of the
Commonwealth, the Equal Rights Amendment (ERA).12[56]
Such a conclusion is analytically unsound and inconsistent with the legislative
history of the ERA.
The central purpose of the ERA was to eradicate discrimination
against women and in favor of men or vice versa. See Attorney Gen. v.
Massachusetts Interscholastic Athletic Ass'n, 378 Mass. 342, 357 (1979).
Consistent with this purpose, we have construed the ERA to prohibit laws that
advantage one sex at the expense of the other, but not laws that treat men and
women equally, id. at 346-349 (assuming that "separate but equal"
treatment of males and females would be constitutionally permissible). The
Massachusetts marriage statute does not subject men to different treatment from
women; each is equally prohibited from precisely the same conduct. See Baker v.
State, 170 Vt. 194, 215 n.13 (1999) ("there is no discrete class subject to
differential treatment solely on the basis of sex"). Compare Commonwealth
v. King, 374 Mass. 5, 16 (1977) (law prohibiting prostitution applied to both
male and female prostitutes and therefore did not discriminate), and Personnel
Adm'r of Mass. v. Feeney, 442 U.S. 256, 274-275 (1979) (declining to
characterize veterans' preference as sex discrimination because it applied to
both male and female veterans), with Attorney Gen. v. Massachusetts
Interscholastic Athletic Ass'n, supra, and Lowell v. Kowalski, 380 Mass. 663
(1980) (where statutes and rules at issue advantaged one sex over another).
Of course, a statute that on its face treats protected groups equally may still
harm, stigmatize, or advantage one over the other. Such was the circumstance in
Loving v. Virginia, 388 U.S. 1 (1967), where the Supreme Court struck down a
State statute that made interracial marriage a crime, as constituting invidious
discrimination on the basis of race. While the statute purported to apply
equally to whites and nonwhites, the Court found that it was intended and
structured to favor one race (white) and disfavor all others (nonwhites). The
statute's legislative history demonstrated that its purpose was not merely to
punish interracial marriage, but to do so for the sole benefit of the white
race. As the Supreme Court readily concluded, the Virginia law was
"designed to maintain White Supremacy." Id. at 11. Consequently, there
was a fit between the class that the law was intended to discriminate against
(nonwhite races) and the classification enjoying heightened protection (race).
By contrast, here there is no evidence that limiting marriage
to opposite-sex couples was motivated by sexism in general or a desire to
disadvantage men or women in particular. Moreover, no one has identified any
harm, burden, disadvantage, or advantage accruing to either gender as a
consequence of the Massachusetts marriage statute. In the absence of such
effect, the statute limiting marriage to couples of the opposite sex does not
violate the ERA's prohibition of sex discrimination.13[57]
This conclusion is buttressed by the legislative history of the ERA, which was
adopted by the voters on November 2, 1976, after being approved by
constitutional conventions of the Legislature on August 15, 1973, (by a vote of
261-0) and May 14, 1975 (by a vote of 217-55).
In anticipation of its adoption, the Legislature enacted
and, on June 21, 1975, the Governor approved a "Resolve providing for an
investigation and study by a special commission relative to the effect of the
ratification of the proposed amendments to the Constitution of the Commonwealth
of Massachusetts and the Constitution of the United States prohibiting
discrimination on account of sex upon the laws, business communities and public
in the Commonwealth." Res. 1975, c. 26. One of the principal tasks of the
commission was to catalog the aspects of the General Laws that would have to be
amended for the statutory code to comply with the mandate of the proposed
amendment that equality not be abridged on the basis of sex.14[58]
On October 19, 1976, just before the general election at which the amendment was
to be considered, the commission filed its Interim Report, which focused on the
effect of the Massachusetts ERA on the laws of the Commonwealth. 1976 Senate
Doc. No. 1689. A section of the report, entitled "Areas Unaffected by the
Equal Rights Amendment," addressed some of the legal regimes that would not
be affected by the adoption of the ERA. One such area was "Homosexual
Marriage," about which the commission stated:
"An equal rights amendment will have no effect upon
the allowance or denial of homosexual marriages. The equal rights amendment is
not concerned with the relationship of two persons of the same sex; it only
addresses those laws or public-related actions which treat persons of opposite
sexes differently. The Washington Court of Appeals has already stated that the
equal rights amendment to its state constitution did not afford a basis for
validating homosexual marriages. In Colorado, the attorney general has likewise
issued an opinion that the state equal rights amendment did not validate
homosexual marriage. There are no cases which have used a state equal rights
amendment to either validate or require the allowance of homosexual
marriages." (Footnotes omitted.) Id . at 21-22.15[59]
The views of the commission were reflected in the
public debate surrounding the passage of the ERA that focused on gender
equality. See, e.g., Referenda reviewed, Boston Globe, Nov. 1, 1976, at 26;
Voters' guide on nine state referendum measures, Boston Herald American, Nov. 1,
1976, at 17. Claims that the ERA might be the basis for validating marriages
between same-sex couples were labelled as "exaggerated" and
"unfounded." For example, before the vote, the Boston Globe published
an editorial discussing and urging favorable action on the ERA. In making its
case, it noted that "[t]hose urging a no vote . . . argue that the
amendment would . . . legitimize marriage between people of the same sex [and
other changes]. In reality, the proposed amendment would require none of these
things. Mass. ballot issues . . . 1 Equal Rights Amendment. Boston Globe, Nov.
1, 1976, at 29. And in the aftermath of the vote, the Boston Globe heralded the
electorate's acceptance of "the arguments of proponents that the proposal
would not result in many far-reaching or threatening changes." Referendums
fared poorly, Boston Globe, Nov. 4, 1976, at 29.
While the court, in interpreting a constitutional amendment,
is not bound to accept either the views of a legislative commission studying and
reporting on the amendment's likely effects, or of public commentary and debate
contemporaneous with its passage, it ought to be wary of completely disregarding
what appears to be the clear intent of the people recently recorded in our
constitutional history. This is particularly so where the plain wording of the
amendment does not require the result it would reach.
C. The marriage statute satisfies the rational basis standard. The burden of
demonstrating that a statute does not satisfy the rational basis standard rests
on the plaintiffs. It is a weighty one. "[A] reviewing court will presume a
statute's validity, and make all rational inferences in favor of it. . . . The
Legislature is not required to justify its classifications, nor provide a record
or finding in support of them." (Citation omitted.) Paro v. Longwood Hosp.,
373 Mass. 645, 650 (1977). The statute "only need[s to] be supported by a
conceivable rational basis." Fine v. Contributory Retirement Appeal Bd.,
401 Mass. 639, 641 (1988). See Massachusetts Fed'n of Teachers v. Board of
Educ., 436 Mass. 763, 771-772 (2002). As this court stated in Shell Oil Co. v.
Revere, 383 Mass. 682, 687-688 (1981):
"[I]t is not the court's function to launch an inquiry to
resolve a debate which has already been settled in the legislative forum. '[I]t
[is] the judge's duty . . . to give effect to the will of the people as
expressed in the statute by their representative body. It is in this way . . .
that the doctrine of separation of powers is given meaning.' Commonwealth v.
Leis, 355 Mass. 189, 202 (1969) (Kirk, J., concurring).
"This respect for the legislative process means that it
is not the province of the court to sit and weigh conflicting evidence
supporting or opposing a legislative enactment. . . .
"Although persons challenging the constitutionality of
legislation may introduce evidence in support of their claim that the
legislation is irrational . . . they will not prevail if 'the question is at
least debatable' in view of the evidence which may have been available to the
Legislature. United States v. Carolene Prods. Co., 304 U.S. 144, 154
(1938)."
The "time tested wisdom of the separation of powers"
requires courts to avoid "judicial legislation in the guise of new
constructions to meet real or supposed new popular viewpoints, preserving always
to the Legislature alone its proper prerogative of adjusting the statutes to
changed conditions." Pielech v. Massasoit Greyhound, Inc., 423 Mass. 534,
539, 540 (1996), cert. denied, 520 U.S. 1131 (1997), quoting Commonwealth v. A
Juvenile, 368 Mass. 580, 595 (1975).
In analyzing whether a statute satisfies the rational basis
standard, we look to the nature of the classification embodied in the enactment,
then to whether the statute serves a legitimate State purpose, and finally to
whether the classification is reasonably related to the furtherance of that
purpose. With this framework, we turn to the challenged statute, G. L. c. 207,
which authorizes local town officials to issue licenses to couples of the
opposite sex authorizing them to enter the institution of civil marriage.
1. Classification. The nature of the classification at issue
is readily apparent. Opposite-sex couples can obtain a license and same-sex
couples cannot. The granting of this license, and the completion of the required
solemnization of the marriage, opens the door to many statutory benefits and
imposes numerous responsibilities. The fact that the statute does not permit
such licenses to be issued to couples of the same sex thus bars them from civil
marriage. The classification is not drawn between men and women or between
heterosexuals and homosexuals, any of whom can obtain a license to marry a
member of the opposite sex; rather, it is drawn between same-sex couples and
opposite-sex couples.
2. State purpose. The court's opinion concedes that the civil marriage statute
serves legitimate State purposes, but further investigation and elaboration of
those purposes is both helpful and necessary.
Civil marriage is the institutional mechanism by which
societies have sanctioned and recognized particular family structures, and the
institution of marriage has existed as one of the fundamental organizing
principles of human society. See C.N. Degler, The Emergence of the Modern
American Family, in The American Family in Social-Historical Perspective 61 (3d
ed. 1983); A.J. Hawkins, Introduction, in Revitalizing the Institution of
Marriage for the Twenty-First Century: An Agenda for Strengthening Marriage xiv
(2002); C. Lasch, Social Pathologists and the Socialization of Reproduction, in
The American Family in Social-Historical Perspective, supra at 80; W.J.
O'Donnell & D.A. Jones, Marriage and Marital Alternatives 1 (1982); L.
Saxton, The Individual, Marriage, and the Family 229-230, 260 (1968); M.A.
Schwartz & B.M. Scott, Marriages and Families: Diversity and Change 4
(1994); Wardle, "Multiply and Replenish": Considering Same-Sex
Marriage in Light of State Interests in Marital Procreation, 24 Harv. J.L. &
Pub. Pol'y 771, 777-780 (2001); J.Q. Wilson, The Marriage Problem: How Our
Culture Has Weakened Families 28, 40, 66-67 (2002). Marriage has not been merely
a contractual arrangement for legally defining the private relationship between
two individuals (although that is certainly part of any marriage). Rather, on an
institutional level, marriage is the "very basis of the whole fabric of
civilized society," J.P. Bishop, Commentaries on the Law of Marriage and
Divorce, and Evidence in Matrimonial Suits § 32 (1852), and it serves many
important political, economic, social, educational, procreational, and personal
functions.
Paramount among its many important functions, the institution
of marriage has systematically provided for the regulation of heterosexual
behavior, brought order to the resulting procreation, and ensured a stable
family structure in which children will be reared, educated, and socialized. See
Milford v. Worcester, 7 Mass. 48, 52 (1810) (civil marriage "intended to
regulate, chasten, and refine, the intercourse between the sexes; and to
multiply, preserve, and improve the species"). See also P. Blumstein &
P. Schwartz, American Couples: Money, Work, Sex 29 (1983); C.N. Degler, supra at
61; G. Douglas, Marriage, Cohabitation, and Parenthood — From Contract to
Status?, in Cross Currents: Family Law and Policy in the United States and
England 223 (2000); S.L. Nock, The Social Costs of De-Institutionalizing
Marriage, in Revitalizing the Institution of Marriage for the Twenty-First
Century: An Agenda for Strengthening Marriage, supra at 7; L. Saxton, supra at
239-240, 242; M.A. Schwartz & B.M. Scott, supra at 4-6; Wardle, supra at
781-796; J.Q. Wilson, supra at 23-32. Admittedly, heterosexual intercourse,
procreation, and child care are not necessarily conjoined (particularly in the
modern age of widespread effective contraception and supportive social welfare
programs), but an orderly society requires some mechanism for coping with the
fact that sexual intercourse commonly results in pregnancy and childbirth. The
institution of marriage is that mechanism.
The institution of marriage provides the important legal and
normative link between heterosexual intercourse and procreation on the one hand
and family responsibilities on the other. The partners in a marriage are
expected to engage in exclusive sexual relations, with children the probable
result and paternity presumed. See G. L. c. 209C, § 6 ("a man is presumed
to be the father of a child . . . if he is or has been married to the mother and
the child was born during the marriage, or within three hundred days after the
marriage was terminated by death, annulment or divorce"). Whereas the
relationship between mother and child is demonstratively and predictably created
and recognizable through the biological process of pregnancy and childbirth,
there is no corresponding process for creating a relationship between father and
child.16[60] Similarly, aside
from an act of heterosexual intercourse nine months prior to childbirth, there
is no process for creating a relationship between a man and a woman as the
parents of a particular child. The institution of marriage fills this void by
formally binding the husband-father to his wife and child, and imposing on him
the responsibilities of fatherhood. See J.Q. Wilson, supra at 23-32. See also P.
Blumstein & P. Schwartz, supra at 29; C.N. Degler, supra at 61; G. Douglas,
supra at 223; S.L. Nock, supra at 7; L. Saxton, supra at 239-240, 242; M.A.
Schwartz & B.M. Scott, supra at 4-6; Wardle, supra at 781-796. The
alternative, a society without the institution of marriage, in which
heterosexual intercourse, procreation, and child care are largely disconnected
processes, would be chaotic.
The marital family is also the foremost setting for the
education and socialization of children. Children learn about the world and
their place in it primarily from those who raise them, and those children
eventually grow up to exert some influence, great or small, positive or
negative, on society. The institution of marriage encourages parents to remain
committed to each other and to their children as they grow, thereby encouraging
a stable venue for the education and socialization of children. See P. Blumstein
& P. Schwartz, supra at 26; C.N. Degler, supra at 61; S.L. Nock, supra at
2-3; C. Lasch, supra at 81; M.A. Schwartz & B.M. Scott, supra at 6-7. More
macroscopically, construction of a family through marriage also formalizes the
bonds between people in an ordered and institutional manner, thereby
facilitating a foundation of interconnectedness and interdependency on which
more intricate stabilizing social structures might be built. See M. Grossberg,
Governing the Hearth: Law and Family in Nineteenth-Century America 10 (1985); C.
Lasch, supra; L. Saxton, supra at 260; J.Q. Wilson, supra at 221.
This court, among others, has consistently acknowledged both
the institutional importance of marriage as an organizing principle of society,
and the State's interest in regulating it. See French v. McAnarney, 290 Mass.
544, 546 (1935) ("Marriage is not merely a contract between the parties. It
is the foundation of the family. It is a social institution of the highest
importance. The Commonwealth has a deep interest that its integrity is not
jeopardized"); Milford v. Worcester, 7 Mass. 48, 52 (1810) ("Marriage,
being essential to the peace and harmony, and to the virtues and improvements of
civil society, it has been, in all well-regulated governments, among the first
attentions of the civil magistrate to regulate [it]"). See also Skinner v.
Oklahoma, 316 U.S. 535, 541 (1942) ("Marriage and procreation are
fundamental to the very existence and survival of the [human] race");
Maynard v. Hill, 125 U.S. 190, 211 (1888) (marriage "is an institution, in
the maintenance of which in its purity the public is deeply interested, for it
is the foundation of the family and of society, without which there would be
neither civilization nor progress"); Murphy v. Ramsey, 114 U.S. 15, 45
(1885) ("no legislation can be supposed more wholesome and necessary in the
founding of a free, self-governing commonwealth . . . than that which seeks to
establish it on the basis of the idea of the family, as consisting in and
springing from the union for life of one man and one woman . . . the sure
foundation of all that is stable and noble in our civilization; the best
guaranty of that reverent morality which is the source of all beneficent
progress in social and political improvement"); Reynolds v. United States,
98 U.S. 145, 165 (1878) ("Upon [marriage] society may be said to be built,
and out of its fruits spring social relations and social obligations and duties,
with which government is necessarily required to deal").
It is undeniably true that dramatic historical shifts in our
cultural, political, and economic landscape have altered some of our traditional
notions about marriage, including the interpersonal dynamics within it,17[61]
the range of responsibilities required of it as an institution,18[62]
and the legal environment in which it exists.19[63]
Nevertheless, the institution of marriage remains the principal weave of our
social fabric. See C.N. Degler, supra at 61; A.J. Hawkins, Introduction, in
Revitalizing the Institution of Marriage for the Twenty-First Century: An Agenda
for Strengthening Marriage xiv (2002); C. Lasch, supra at 80; W.J. O'Donnell
& D.A. Jones, Marriage and Marital Alternatives 1 (1982); L. Saxton, supra
at 229-230, 260; M.A. Schwartz & B.M. Scott, supra at 4; Wardle, supra at
777-780; J.Q. Wilson, supra at 28, 40, 66-67. A family defined by heterosexual
marriage continues to be the most prevalent social structure into which the vast
majority of children are born, nurtured, and prepared for productive
participation in civil society, see Children's Living Arrangements and
Characteristics: March, 2002, United States Census Bureau Current Population
Reports at 3 (June, 2003) (in 2002, 69% of children lived with two married
parents, 23% lived with their mother, 5% lived with their father, and 4% lived
in households with neither parent present).
It is difficult to imagine a State purpose more important and legitimate than
ensuring, promoting, and supporting an optimal social structure within which to
bear and raise children. At the very least, the marriage statute continues to
serve this important State purpose.20[64]
3. Rational relationship. The question we must turn to next is
whether the statute, construed as limiting marriage to couples of the opposite
sex, remains a rational way to further that purpose. Stated differently, we ask
whether a conceivable rational basis exists on which the Legislature could
conclude that continuing to limit the institution of civil marriage to members
of the opposite sex furthers the legitimate purpose of ensuring, promoting, and
supporting an optimal social structure for the bearing and raising of
children.21[65]
In considering whether such a rational basis exists, we defer
to the decision-making process of the Legislature, and must make deferential
assumptions about the information that it might consider and on which it may
rely. See Shell Oil Co. v. Revere, 383 Mass. 682, 688 (1981) (court considers
"evidence which may have been available to the Legislature" [emphasis
added]); Slome v. Chief of Police of Fitchburg, 304 Mass. 187, 189 (1939)
("any rational basis of fact that can be reasonably conceived" may
support legislative finding); Mutual Loan Co. v. Martell, 200 Mass. 482, 487
(1909), aff'd, 222 U.S. 225 (1911) ("Legislature may be supposed to have
known" relevant facts).
We must assume that the Legislature (1) might conclude that
the institution of civil marriage has successfully and continually provided this
structure over several centuries22[66];
(2) might consider and credit studies that document negative consequences that
too often follow children either born outside of marriage or raised in
households lacking either a father or a mother figure,23[67]
and scholarly commentary contending that children and families develop best when
mothers and fathers are partners in their parenting24[68];
and (3) would be familiar with many recent studies that variously support the
proposition that children raised in intact families headed by same-sex couples
fare as well on many measures as children raised in similar families headed by
opposite-sex couples25[69];
support the proposition that children of same-sex couples fare worse on some
measures26[70]; or reveal
notable differences between the two groups of children that warrant further
study.27[71]
We must also assume that the Legislature would be aware of the
critiques of the methodologies used in virtually all of the comparative studies
of children raised in these different environments, cautioning that the sampling
populations are not representative, that the observation periods are too limited
in time,28[72] that the
empirical data are unreliable, and that the hypotheses are too infused with
political or agenda driven bias. See, e.g., R. Lerner & A.K. Nagai, No
Basis: What the Studies Don't Tell Us About Same-Sex Parenting, Marriage Law
Project (Jan. 2001) (criticizing forty-nine studies on same-sex parenting --
at least twenty-six of which were cited by amici in this case -- as suffering
from flaws in formulation of hypotheses, use of experimental controls, use of
measurements, sampling and statistical testing, and finding false negatives);
Stacey, (How) Does the Sexual Orientation of Parents Matter, 66 Am. Soc. Rev.
159, 159-166 (2001) (highlighting problems with sampling pools, lack of
longitudinal studies, and political hypotheses).
Taking all of this available information into account, the
Legislature could rationally conclude that a family environment with married
opposite-sex parents remains the optimal social structure in which to bear
children, and that the raising of children by same-sex couples, who by
definition cannot be the two sole biological parents of a child and cannot
provide children with a parental authority figure of each gender,29[73]
presents an alternative structure for child rearing that has not yet proved
itself beyond reasonable scientific dispute to be as optimal as the biologically
based marriage norm. See Baker v. State, 170 Vt. 194, 222 (1999)
("conceivable that the Legislature could conclude that opposite-sex
partners offer advantages in th[e] area [of child rearing], although . . .
experts disagree and the answer is decidedly uncertain"). Cf. Marcoux v.
Attorney Gen., 375 Mass. 63, 65 (1978). Working from the assumption that a
recognition of same-sex marriages will increase the number of children
experiencing this alternative, the Legislature could conceivably conclude that
declining to recognize same-sex marriages remains prudent until empirical
questions about its impact on the upbringing of children are resolved.30[74]
The fact that the Commonwealth currently allows same-sex
couples to adopt, see Adoption of Tammy, 416 Mass. 205 (1993), does not affect
the rationality of this conclusion. The eligibility of a child for adoption
presupposes that at least one of the child's biological parents is unable or
unwilling, for some reason, to participate in raising the child. In that sense,
society has "lost" the optimal setting in which to raise that child --
it is simply not available. In these circumstances, the principal and overriding
consideration is the "best interests of the child," considering his or
her unique circumstances and the options that are available for that child. The
objective is an individualized determination of the best environment for a
particular child, where the normative social structure -- a home with both the
child's biological father and mother -- is not an option. That such a focused
determination may lead to the approval of a same-sex couple's adoption of a
child does not mean that it would be irrational for a legislator, in fashioning
statutory laws that cannot make such individualized determinations, to conclude
generally that being raised by a same-sex couple has not yet been shown to be
the absolute equivalent of being raised by one's married biological parents.
That the State does not preclude different types of families
from raising children does not mean that it must view them all as equally
optimal and equally deserving of State endorsement and support.31[75]
For example, single persons are allowed to adopt children, but the fact that the
Legislature permits single-parent adoption does not mean that it has endorsed
single parenthood as an optimal setting in which to raise children or views it
as the equivalent of being raised by both of one's biological parents.32[76]
The same holds true with respect to same-sex couples -- the fact that they may
adopt children means only that the Legislature has concluded that they may
provide an acceptable setting in which to raise children who cannot be raised by
both of their biological parents. The Legislature may rationally permit adoption
by same-sex couples yet harbor reservations as to whether parenthood by same-sex
couples should be affirmatively encouraged to the same extent as parenthood by
the heterosexual couple whose union produced the child.33[77]
In addition, the Legislature could conclude that redefining
the institution of marriage to permit same-sex couples to marry would impair the
State's interest in promoting and supporting heterosexual marriage as the social
institution that it has determined best normalizes, stabilizes, and links the
acts of procreation and child rearing. While the plaintiffs argue that they only
want to take part in the same stabilizing institution, the Legislature
conceivably could conclude that permitting their participation would have the
unintended effect of undermining to some degree marriage's ability to serve its
social purpose. See Commonwealth v. Stowell, 389 Mass. 171, 175 (1983) (given
State's broad concern with institution of marriage, it has "legitimate
interest in prohibiting conduct which may threaten that institution").
As long as marriage is limited to opposite-sex couples who can
at least theoretically procreate, society is able to communicate a consistent
message to its citizens that marriage is a (normatively) necessary part of their
procreative endeavor; that if they are to procreate, then society has endorsed
the institution of marriage as the environment for it and for the subsequent
rearing of their children; and that benefits are available explicitly to create
a supportive and conducive atmosphere for those purposes. If society proceeds
similarly to recognize marriages between same-sex couples who cannot procreate,
it could be perceived as an abandonment of this claim, and might result in the
mistaken view that civil marriage has little to do with procreation: just as the
potential of procreation would not be necessary for a marriage to be valid,
marriage would not be necessary for optimal procreation and child rearing to
occur.34[78] In essence, the
Legislature could conclude that the consequence of such a policy shift would be
a diminution in society's ability to steer the acts of procreation and child
rearing into their most optimal setting.35[79]
Hall-Omar Baking Co. v. Commissioner of Labor & Indus., 344 Mass. 695, 700
(1962) ("Legislative classification is valid if it is rational and bears
some relationship to the object intended to be accomplished" [emphasis
added]).
The court recognizes this concern, but brushes it aside with the assumption that
permitting same-sex couples to marry "will not diminish the validity or
dignity of opposite-sex marriage," ante at , and that "we have no
doubt that marriage will continue to be a vibrant and revered institution."
Ante at . Whether the court is correct in its assumption is irrelevant. What is
relevant is that such predicting is not the business of the courts. A rational
Legislature, given the evidence, could conceivably come to a different
conclusion, or could at least harbor rational concerns about possible unintended
consequences of a dramatic redefinition of marriage.36[80]
There is no question that many same-sex couples are capable of
being good parents, and should be (and are) permitted to be so. The policy
question that a legislator must resolve is a different one, and turns on an
assessment of whether the marriage structure proposed by the plaintiffs will,
over time, if endorsed and supported by the State, prove to be as stable and
successful a model as the one that has formed a cornerstone of our society since
colonial times, or prove to be less than optimal, and result in consequences,
perhaps now unforeseen, adverse to the State's legitimate interest in promoting
and supporting the best possible social structure in which children should be
born and raised. Given the critical importance of civil marriage as an
organizing and stabilizing institution of society, it is eminently rational for
the Legislature to postpone making fundamental changes to it until such time as
there is unanimous scientific evidence, or popular consensus, or both, that such
changes can safely be made.37[81]
There is no reason to believe that legislative processes are
inadequate to effectuate legal changes in response to evolving evidence, social
values, and views of fairness on the subject of same-sex relationships.38[82]
Deliberate consideration of, and incremental responses to rapidly evolving
scientific and social understanding is the norm of the political process -- that
it may seem painfully slow to those who are already persuaded by the arguments
in favor of change is not a sufficient basis to conclude that the processes are
constitutionally infirm. See, e.g., Massachusetts Fed'n of Teachers v. Board of
Educ., 436 Mass. 763, 778 (2002); Mobil Oil v. Attorney Gen., 361 Mass. 401, 417
(1972) (Legislature may proceed piecemeal in addressing perceived injustices or
problems). The advancement of the rights, privileges, and protections afforded
to homosexual members of our community in the last three decades has been
significant, and there is no reason to believe that that evolution will not
continue. Changes of attitude in the civic, social, and professional communities
have been even more profound. Thirty years ago, The Diagnostic and Statistical
Manual, the seminal handbook of the American Psychiatric Association, still
listed homosexuality as a mental disorder. Today, the Massachusetts Psychiatric
Society, the American Psychoanalytic Association, and many other psychiatric,
psychological, and social science organizations have joined in an amicus brief
on behalf of the plaintiffs' cause. A body of experience and evidence has
provided the basis for change, and that body continues to mount. The Legislature
is the appropriate branch, both constitutionally and practically, to consider
and respond to it. It is not enough that we as Justices might be personally of
the view that we have learned enough to decide what is best. So long as the
question is at all debatable, it must be the Legislature that decides. The
marriage statute thus meets the requirements of the rational basis test. Accord
Standhardt v. Superior Court, 77 P.3d 451 (Ariz. Ct. App. 2003) (marriage
statutes rationally related to State's legitimate interest in encouraging
procreation and child rearing within marriage); Baker v. Nelson, 291 Minn. 310,
313 (1971) ("equal protection clause of the Fourteenth Amendment, like the
due process clause, is not offended by the state's classification of persons
authorized to marry"); Singer v. Hara, 11 Wash. App. 247, 262-263 (1974)
("There can be no doubt that there exists a rational basis for the state to
limit the definition of marriage to exclude same-sex relationships").
D. Conclusion. While "[t]he Massachusetts Constitution
protects matters of personal liberty against government incursion as zealously,
and often more so, than does the Federal Constitution," ante at - , this
case is not about government intrusions into matters of personal liberty. It is
not about the rights of same-sex couples to choose to live together, or to be
intimate with each other, or to adopt and raise children together. It is about
whether the State must endorse and support their choices by changing the
institution of civil marriage to make its benefits, obligations, and
responsibilities applicable to them. While the courageous efforts of many have
resulted in increased dignity, rights, and respect for gay and lesbian members
of our community, the issue presented here is a profound one, deeply rooted in
social policy, that must, for now, be the subject of legislative not judicial
action.
FOOTNOTES:
[1] Julie Goodridge, David Wilson, Robert Compton, Michael Horgan, Edward Balmelli, Maureen Brodoff, Ellen Wade, Gary Chalmers, Richard Linnell, Heidi Norton, Gina Smith, Gloria Bailey, and Linda Davies.
[2] Commissioner of Public Health.
[3] For American appellate courts that have recently addressed this issue, see Standhardt v. Superior Court, 77 P.3d 451 (Ariz. Ct. App. 2003); Dean v. District of Columbia, 653 A.2d 307 (D.C. 1995); Baehr v. Lewin, 74 Haw. 530 (1993); Baker v. State, 170 Vt. 194, 242 (1999). Earlier cases include Adams v. Howerton, 486 F. Supp. 1119 (C.D. Cal. 1980), aff'd, 673 F.2d 1036 (9th Cir.), cert. denied, 458 U.S. 1111 (1982); Jones v. Hallahan, 501 S.W.2d 588 (Ky. Ct. App. 1973); Baker v. Nelson, 291 Minn. 310 (1971), appeal dismissed, 409 U.S. 810 (1972); Singer v. Hara, 11 Wash. App. 247 (1974). See also Halpern v. Toronto (City), 172 O.A.C. 276 (2003); Egale Canada, Inc. v. Canada (Attorney Gen.), 13 B.C.L.R. (4th) 1 (2003).
[4] General Laws c. 207, § 37, provides: "The commissioner of public health shall furnish to the clerk or registrar of every town a printed list of all legal impediments to marriage, and the clerk or registrar shall forthwith post and thereafter maintain it in a conspicuous place in his office." The record does not reveal whether any of the clerks' offices that considered the plaintiffs' applications for a marriage license had posted such a list of impediments, or whether such list included as an impediment that the applicants are of the same sex.
[5] The plaintiffs alleged that they met all of the facial qualifications to obtain marriage licenses pursuant to G. L. c. 207, and the department does not contest this assertion.
[6] The complaint alleged various circumstances in which the absence of the full legal protections of civil marriage has harmed them and their children. For example, Hillary and Julie Goodridge alleged that, when Julie gave birth to their daughter (whom Hillary subsequently coadopted) during a delivery that required the infant's transfer to neonatal intensive care, Hillary "had difficulty gaining access to Julie and their newborn daughter at the hospital"; Gary Chalmers and Richard Linnell alleged that "Gary pays for a family health insurance policy at work which covers only him and their daughter because Massachusetts law does not consider Rich to be a 'dependent.' This means that their household must purchase a separate individual policy of health insurance for Rich at considerable expense. . . . Gary has a pension plan at work, but under state law, because he is a municipal employee, that plan does not allow him the same range of options in providing for his beneficiary that a married spouse has and thus he cannot provide the same security to his family that a married person could if he should predecease Rich."
[7]
Article 1, as amended by art. 106 of the Amendments to the Massachusetts
Constitution, provides: "All people are born free and equal and have
certain natural, essential and unalienable rights; among which may be reckoned
the right of enjoying and defending their lives and liberties; that of
acquiring, possessing and protecting property; in fine, that of seeking and
obtaining their safety and happiness. Equality under the law shall not be denied
or abridged because of sex, race, color, creed or national origin."
Article 6 provides: "No man, nor corporation, or
association of men, have any other title to obtain advantages, or particular and
exclusive privileges, distinct from those of the community, than what arises
from the consideration of services rendered to the public . . . ."
Article 7 provides: "Government is instituted for the
common good; for the protection, safety, prosperity, and happiness of the
people; and not for the profit, honor, or private interest of any one man,
family or class of men: Therefore the people alone have an incontestable,
unalienable, and indefeasible right to institute government; and to reform,
alter, or totally change the same, when their protection, safety, prosperity and
happiness require it."
Article 10 provides, in relevant part: "Each individual
of the society has a right to be protected by it in the enjoyment of his life,
liberty and property, according to standing laws . . . ."
Article 12 provides, in relevant part: "[N]o subject
shall be . . . deprived of his property, immunities, or privileges, put out of
the protection of the law . . . or deprived of his life, liberty, or estate, but
by the judgment of his peers, or the law of the land."
Article 16, as amended by art. 77 of the Amendments, provides,
in relevant part: "The right of free speech shall not be abridged."
Part II, c. 1, § 1, art. 4, as amended by art. 112, provides, in
pertinent part, that "full power and authority are hereby given and granted
to the said general court, from time to time, to make, ordain, and establish all
manner of wholesome and reasonable orders, laws, statutes, and ordinances,
directions and instructions, either with penalties or without; so as the same be
not repugnant or contrary to this constitution, as they shall judge to be for
the good and welfare of this Commonwealth."
[8] The department claims that the plaintiffs have waived their art. 12 and art. 16 claims on appeal. Because our holding today does not turn on art. 12 or art. 16, we do not consider the department's waiver argument.
[9] The marital forms forwarded by the clerk or register must contain the "date of record, date and place of marriage, name, residence and official station of the person by whom solemnized; for each of the parties to be married the name, date and place of birth, residence, age, number of the marriage, as first or second, and if previously married, whether widowed or divorced, and the birth-given names of their parents." G. L. c. 46, § 1.
[10] "The record of a marriage made and kept as provided by law by the person by whom the marriage was solemnized, or by the clerk or registrar, or a copy thereof duly certified, shall be prima facie evidence of such marriage." G. L. c. 207, § 45. A "certificate of the [c]ommissioner's copy, signed by the [c]ommissioner or the [r]egistar, is admissible as evidence of the record." Secretary of the Commonwealth v. City Clerk of Lowell, 373 Mass. 178, 181-182 (1977).
[11] We use the terms "same sex" and "opposite sex" when characterizing the couples in question, because these terms are more accurate in this context than the terms "homosexual" or "heterosexual," although at times we use those terms when we consider them appropriate. Nothing in our marriage law precludes people who identify themselves (or who are identified by others) as gay, lesbian, or bisexual from marrying persons of the opposite sex. See Baehr v. Lewin, 74 Haw. 530, 543 n.11, 547 n.14 (1993).
[12] "The term public welfare has never been and cannot be precisely defined. Sometimes it has been said to include public convenience, comfort, peace and order, prosperity, and similar concepts, but not to include 'mere expediency.'" Opinion of the Justices, 333 Mass. 773, 778 (1955).
[13] For example, married persons face substantial restrictions, simply because they are married, on their ability freely to dispose of their assets. See, e.g., G. L. c. 208, § 34 (providing for the payment of alimony and the equitable division of property on divorce); G. L. c. 191, § 15, and G. L. c. 189 (rights of elective share and dower).
[14] Civil marriage enjoys a dual and in some sense paradoxical status as both a State-conferred benefit (with its attendant obligations) and a multi-faceted personal interest of "fundamental importance." Zablocki v. Redhail, 434 U.S. 376, 383 (1978). As a practical matter, the State could not abolish civil marriage without chaotic consequences. The "right to marry," id. at 387, is different from rights deemed "fundamental" for equal protection and due process purposes because the State could, in theory, abolish all civil marriage while it cannot, for example, abolish all private property rights.
[15] The department argues that this case concerns the rights of couples (same sex and opposite sex), not the rights of individuals. This is incorrect. The rights implicated in this case are at the core of individual privacy and autonomy. See, e.g., Loving v. Virginia, 388 U.S. 1, 12 (1967) ("Under our Constitution, the freedom to marry or not marry, a person of another race resides with the individual and cannot be infringed by the State"); Perez v. Sharp, 32 Cal. 2d 711, 716 (1948) ("The right to marry is the right of individuals, not of racial groups"). See also A.Z. v. B.Z., 431 Mass. 150, 162 (2000), quoting Moore v. East Cleveland, 431 U.S. 494, 499 (1977) (noting "freedom of personal choice in matters of marriage and family life"). While two individuals who wish to marry may be equally aggrieved by State action denying them that opportunity, they do not "share" the liberty and equality interests at stake.
[16] The department argues that the Loving decision did not profoundly alter the by-then common conception of marriage because it was decided at a time when antimiscegenation statutes were in "full-scale retreat." But the relationship the department draws between popular consensus and the constitutionality of a statute oppressive to a minority group ignores the successful constitutional challenges to an antimiscegenation statute, initiated some twenty years earlier. When the Supreme Court of California decided Perez v. Sharp, 32 Cal. 2d 711, 728 (1948), a precursor to Loving, racial inequality was rampant and normative, segregation in public and private institutions was commonplace, the civil rights movement had not yet been launched, and the "separate but equal" doctrine of Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U.S. 537 (1896), was still good law. The lack of popular consensus favoring integration (including interracial marriage) did not deter the Supreme Court of California from holding that that State's antimiscegenation statute violated the plaintiffs' constitutional rights. Neither the Perez court nor the Loving Court was content to permit an unconstitutional situation to fester because the remedy might not reflect a broad social consensus.
[17] Recently, the United States Supreme Court has reaffirmed that the Constitution prohibits a State from wielding its formidable power to regulate conduct in a manner that demeans basic human dignity, even though that statutory discrimination may enjoy broad public support. The Court struck down a statute criminalizing sodomy. See Lawrence, supra at 2478 ("The liberty protected by the Constitution allows homosexual persons the right to make this choice").
[18] We have recognized that our Constitution may more extensively protect individual rights than the Federal Constitution in widely different contexts. See, e.g., Horsemen's Benevolent & Protective Ass'n v. State Racing Comm'n, 403 Mass. 692 (1989) (freedom from intrusive drug testing in highly regulated industry); Cepulonis v. Secretary of the Commonwealth, 389 Mass. 930 (1983) (inmates' right to register to vote); Batchelder v. Allied Stores Int'l, Inc., 388 Mass. 83 (1983) (freedom to solicit signatures for ballot access in public election); Moe v. Secretary of Admin. & Fin., 382 Mass. 629 (1981) (right to State Medicaid payment for medically necessary abortions); Coffee-Rich, Inc. v. Commissioner of Pub. Health, 348 Mass. 414 (1965) (freedom to pursue one's lawful business).
[19] The Massachusetts Constitution empowers the General Court to enact only those orders, laws, statutes, and ordinances "wholesome and reasonable," that are not "repugnant or contrary" to the Constitution, and that, in the Legislature's judgment, advance the "good and welfare" of the Commonwealth, its government, and all of its subjects. Part II, c. 1, § 1, art. 4. See Opinion of the Justices, 360 Mass. 877, 883 (1971), quoting Jones v. Robbins, 8 Gray 329, 343 (1857) (powers vested in government are set down in the Massachusetts Constitution "in a few plain, clear and intelligible propositions, for the better guidance and control, both of legislators and magistrates").
[20] Not every asserted rational relationship is a "conceivable" one, and rationality review is not "toothless." Murphy v. Commissioner of the Dep't of Indus. Accs., 415 Mass. 218, 233 (1993), citing Mathews v. Lucas, 427 U.S. 495, 510 (1976). Statutes have failed rational basis review even in circumstances where no fundamental right or "suspect" classification is implicated. See, e.g., Murphy v. Commissioner of the Dep't of Indus. Accs., 415 Mass. 218, 226-227 (1993) (fee imposed on retention of counsel in administrative proceedings); Secretary of the Commonwealth v. City Clerk of Lowell, 373 Mass. 178, 186 (1977) (selection of surname for nonmarital child); Aetna Cas. & Sur. Co. v. Commissioner of Ins., 358 Mass. 272, 280-281 (1970) (automobile insurance ratesetting); Coffee-Rich, Inc. v. Commissioner of Pub. Health, 348 Mass. 414, 422 (1965) (sale of wholesome product); Mansfield Beauty Academy, Inc. v. Board of Registration of Hairdressers, 326 Mass. 624, 627 (1951) (right to charge for materials furnished to models by trade school); Opinion of the Justices, 322 Mass. 755, 760-761 (1948) (proposed statute concerning regulating cemeteries); Boston Elevated Ry. v. Commonwealth, 310 Mass. 528, 556-557 (1942) (legislation impairing contract right); Durgin v. Minot, 203 Mass. 26, 28 (1909) (statute authorizing certain board of health regulations).
[21] Article 1 of the Massachusetts Constitution specifically prohibits sex-based discrimination. See post at (Greaney, J., concurring). We have not previously considered whether "sexual orientation" is a "suspect" classification. Our resolution of this case does not require that inquiry here.
[22] Our marriage law does recognize that the inability to participate in intimate relations may have a bearing on one of the central expectations of marriage. Since the earliest days of the Commonwealth, the divorce statutes have permitted (but not required) a spouse to choose to divorce his or her impotent mate. See St. 1785, c. 69, § 3. While infertility is not a ground to void or terminate a marriage, impotency (the inability to engage in sexual intercourse) is, at the election of the disaffected spouse. See G. L. c. 207, § 14 (annulment); G. L. c. 208, § 1 (divorce). Cf. Martin v. Otis, 233 Mass. 491, 495 (1919) ("impotency does not render a marriage void, but only voidable at the suit of the party conceiving himself or herself to be wronged"); Smith v. Smith, 171 Mass. 404, 408 (1898) (marriage nullified because husband's incurable syphilis "leaves him no foundation on which the marriage relation could properly rest"). See also G. L. c. 207, § 28A. However, in Hanson v. Hanson, 287 Mass. 154 (1934), a decree of annulment for nonconsummation was reversed where the wife knew before the marriage that her husband had syphilis and voluntarily chose to marry him. We held that, given the circumstances of the wife's prior knowledge of the full extent of the disease and her consent to be married, the husband's condition did not go "to the essence" of the marriage. Id. at 159.
[23] It is hardly surprising that civil marriage developed historically as a means to regulate heterosexual conduct and to promote child rearing, because until very recently unassisted heterosexual relations were the only means short of adoption by which children could come into the world, and the absence of widely available and effective contraceptives made the link between heterosexual sex and procreation very strong indeed. Punitive notions of illegitimacy, see Powers v. Wilkinson, 399 Mass. 650, 661 (1987), and of homosexual identity, see Lawrence, supra at 2478-2479, further cemented the common and legal understanding of marriage as an unquestionably heterosexual institution. But it is circular reasoning, not analysis, to maintain that marriage must remain a heterosexual institution because that is what it historically has been. As one dissent acknowledges, in "the modern age," "heterosexual intercourse, procreation, and childcare are not necessarily conjoined." Post at (Cordy, J., dissenting).
[24] Adoption and certain insurance coverage for assisted reproductive technology are available to married couples, same- sex couples, and single individuals alike. See G. L. c. 210, § 1; Adoption of Tammy, 416 Mass. 205 (1993) (adoption); G. L. c. 175, § 47H; G. L. c. 176A, § 8K; G. L. c. 176B, § 4J; and G. L. c. 176G, § 4 (insurance coverage). See also Woodward v. Commissioner of Social Sec., 435 Mass. 536, 546 (2002) (posthumous reproduction); Culliton v. Beth Israel Deaconness Med. Ctr., 435 Mass. 285, 293 (2001) (gestational surrogacy).
[25] Because our laws expressly or implicitly sanction so many kinds of opposite-sex marriages that do not or will never result in unassisted reproduction, it is erroneous to claim, as the dissent does, that the "theoretical[]" procreative capacity of opposite-sex couples, post at (Cordy, J., dissenting), sufficiently justifies excluding from civil marriage same-sex couples who actually have children.
[26] The claim that the constitutional rights to bear and raise a child are "not implicated or infringed" by the marriage ban, post at (Cordy, J., dissenting), does not stand up to scrutiny. The absolute foreclosure of the marriage option for the class of parents and would-be parents at issue here imposes a heavy burden on their decision to have and raise children that is not suffered by any other class of parent.
[27] It is also true that civil marriage creates legal dependency between spouses, which is simply not available to unmarried couples. See Part III A, supra.
[28] Justice Cordy suggests that we have "transmuted the 'right' to marry into a right to change the institution of marriage itself," post at (Cordy, J., dissenting), because marriage is intimately tied to the reproductive systems of the marriage partners and to the "optimal" mother and father setting for child rearing. Id. That analysis hews perilously close to the argument, long repudiated by the Legislature and the courts, that men and women are so innately and fundamentally different that their respective "proper spheres" can be rigidly and universally delineated. An abundance of legislative enactments and decisions of this court negate any such stereotypical premises.
[29] We are concerned only with the withholding of the benefits, protections, and obligations of civil marriage from a certain class of persons for invalid reasons. Our decision in no way limits the rights of individuals to refuse to marry persons of the same sex for religious or any other reasons. It in no way limits the personal freedom to disapprove of, or to encourage others to disapprove of, same-sex marriage. Our concern, rather, is whether historical, cultural, religious, or other reasons permit the State to impose limits on personal beliefs concerning whom a person should marry.
[30] Justice Cordy's dissenting opinion, post at - and nn. 24-28 (Cordy, J., dissenting), makes much of the current "battle of the experts" concerning the possible long-term effects on children of being raised in households headed by same-sex parents. We presume that the Legislature is aware of these studies, see Mutual Loan Co. v. Martell, 200 Mass. 482, 487 (1909), aff'd, 222 U.S. 225 (1911), and has drawn the conclusion that a child's best interest is not harmed by being raised and nurtured by same-sex parents. See G. L. c. 210, § 7. See also Adoption of Tammy, 416 Mass. 205 (1993); 110 Code Mass. Regs. § 1.09 (3) (2000) ("The Department [of Social Services] shall not deny to any person the opportunity to become an adoptive or foster parent, on the basis of the . . . sexual orientation . . . of the person, or of the child, involved"). Either the Legislature's openness to same-sex parenting is rational in light of its paramount interests in promoting children's well-being, or irrational in light of its so-called conclusion that a household headed by opposite-sex married parents is the "optimal" setting for raising children. See post at (Cordy, J., dissenting). We give full credit to the Legislature for enacting a statutory scheme of child-related laws that is coherent, consistent, and harmonious. See New England Div. of the Am. Cancer Soc'y v. Commissioner of Admin., 437 Mass. 172, 180 (2002).
[31]
If total deference to the Legislature were the case, the judiciary would be
stripped of its constitutional authority to decide challenges to statutes
pertaining to marriage, child rearing, and family relationships, and,
conceivably, unconstitutional laws that provided for the forced sterilization of
habitual criminals; prohibited miscegenation; required court approval for the
marriage of persons with child support obligations; compelled a pregnant
unmarried minor to obtain the consent of both parents before undergoing an
abortion; and made sodomy a criminal offense, to name just a few, would stand.
Indeed, every State court that has recently considered the
issue we decide today has exercised its duty in the same way, by carefully
scrutinizing the statutory ban on same-sex marriages in light of relevant State
constitutional provisions. See Brause vs. Bureau of Vital Statistics, No.
3AN-95-6562CJ (Alaska Super. Ct., Feb. 27, 1998) (concluding marriage statute
violated right to privacy provision in Alaska Constitution) (superseded by
constitutional amendment, art. I, § 25 of the Constitution of Alaska);
Baehr v. Lewin, 74 Haw. 530, 571-580 (1993) (concluding marriage statute
implicated Hawaii Constitution's equal protection clause; remanding case to
lower court for further proceedings); Baker v. State, 170 Vt. 194, 197-198
(1999) (concluding marriage statute violated Vermont Constitution's common
benefits clause). But see Standhardt v. Superior Court, 77 P.3d 451 (Ariz. Ct.
App. 2003) (marriage statute does not violate liberty interests under either
Federal or Arizona Constitution). See also Halpern v. Toronto (City), 172 O.A.C.
276 (2003) (concluding marriage statute violated equal protection provisions of
Canada's Charter of Rights and Freedoms); Eagle Canada, Inc. v. Canada (Attorney
Gen.), 13 B.C.L.R. (4th) 1 (2003) (same).
[32] One prominent historian of marriage notes, for example, that in the Nineteenth Century, the Reverend Theodore Woolsey led the charge against expanding the grounds for divorce, arguing that the "the only divinely approved (and therefore truly legitimate) reason for divorce was adultery" and that only the innocent party to a marriage terminated by reason of adultery be permitted to remarry. Cott, Public Vows: A History of Marriage and the Nation 106 (2000). See id. at 44-45, for a general discussion of resistance to the demise of antimiscegenation laws.
[33] It is not dispositive, for purposes of our constitutional analysis, whether the Legislature, at the time it incorporated the common-law definition of marriage into the first marriage laws nearly three centuries ago, did so with the intent of discriminating against or harming persons who wish to marry another of the same sex. We are not required to impute an invidious intent to the Legislature in determining that a statute of long standing has no applicability to present circumstances or violates the rights of individuals under the Massachusetts Constitution. That the Legislature may have intended what at the time of enactment was a perfectly reasonable form of discrimination -- or a result not recognized as a form of discrimination -- was not enough to salvage from later constitutional challenge laws burdening nonmarital children or denying women's equal partnership in marriage. See, e.g., Trimble v. Gordon, 430 U.S. 762 (1977) (nonmarital children); Angelini v. OMD Corp., 410 Mass. 653, 662, 663 (1987) ("The traditional common law rules which discriminated against children born out of wedlock have been discarded" and "[w]e have recognized that placing additional burdens on [nonmarital] children is unfair because they are not responsible for their [status]"); Silvia v. Silvia, 9 Mass. App. Ct. 339, 340-341 (1980) (there now exists "a comprehensive statutory and common law pattern which places marital and parental obligations on both the husband and wife"). We are concerned with the operation of challenged laws on the parties before us, and we do not inhibit our inquiry on the ground that a statute's original enactors had a benign or at the time constitutionally unassailable purpose. See Colo v. Treasurer & Receiver Gen., 378 Mass. 550, 557 (1979), quoting Walz v. Tax Comm'n of the City of N.Y., 397 U.S. 664, 678 (1970) ("the mere fact that a certain practice has gone unchallenged for a long period of time cannot alone immunize it from constitutional invalidity, 'even when that span of time covers our entire national existence and indeed predates it'"); Merit Oil Co. v. Director of Div. on the Necessaries of Life, 319 Mass. 301, 305 (1946) (constitutional contours of State's regulatory authority coextensive "with the changing needs of society").
[34] Similarly, no one argues that the restrictions on incestuous or polygamous marriages are so dependent on the marriage restriction that they too should fall if the marriage restriction falls. Nothing in our opinion today should be construed as relaxing or abrogating the consanguinity or polygamy prohibitions of our marriage laws. See G. L. c. 207, §§ 1, 2, and 4. Rather, the statutory provisions concerning consanguinity or polygamous marriages shall be construed in a gender neutral manner. See Califano v. Westcott, 443 U.S. 76, 92-93 (1979) (construing word "father" in unconstitutional, underinclusive provision to mean "parent"); Browne's Case, 322 Mass. 429, 430 (1948) (construing masculine pronoun "his" to include feminine pronoun "her"). See also G. L. c. 4, § 6, Fourth ("words of one gender may be construed to include the other gender and the neuter" unless such construction would be "inconsistent with the manifest intent of the law-making body or repugnant to the context of the same statute").
[35]1 It makes no difference that the referenced decisions consider the right to marry in the context of the Fourteenth Amendment to the United States Constitution rather than in the context of our Constitution. As explained by the court, ante at n.18, a fundamental right under the Federal Constitution enjoys at least a comparable measure of protection under our State Constitution. See Moe v. Secretary of Admin. & Fin., 382 Mass. 629, 651 (1981).
[36]2
In her separate opinion in Baker v. State, 170 Vt. 194, 253 (1999) (Johnson, J.,
concurring in part and dissenting in part), Justice Johnson described the equal
protection defect in Vermont's marriage statutes in a slightly different, but no
less persuasive, fashion:
"A woman is denied the right to marry another woman
because her would-be partner is a woman, not because one or both are lesbians.
Similarly, a man is denied the right to marry another man because his would-be
partner is a man, not because one or both are gay. Thus, an individual's right
to marry a person of the same sex is prohibited solely on the basis of sex, not
on the basis of sexual orientation. Indeed, sexual orientation does not appear
as a qualification for marriage under the marriage statutes. The State makes no
inquiry into the sexual practices or identities of a couple seeking a
license."
[37]3
Some might say that the use of the so-called strict scrutiny formula is too
facile in the sense that, once a court focuses on the formula as a dispositional
tool, the result is automatically preordained -- the statute will fail because
the State cannot possibly sustain its heavy burden to overcome the presumption
of arbitrary and invidious discrimination. This is not so. See, e.g., Blixt v.
Blixt, 437 Mass. 649, 656-657 (2002), cert. denied, 537 U.S. 1189 (2003)
(concluding G. L. c. 119, § 39D, grandparent visitation statute,
furthered compelling State interest in mitigating potential harm to children in
nonintact families).
[38]4 The argument, made by some in the case, that legalization of same-sex marriage in Massachusetts will be used by persons in other States as a tool to obtain recognition of a marriage in their State that is otherwise unlawful, is precluded by the provisions of G. L. c. 207, §§ 11, 12, and 13.
[39]5 Because marriage is, by all accounts, the cornerstone of our social structure, as well as the defining relationship in our personal lives, confining eligibility in the institution, and all of its accompanying benefits and responsibilities, to opposite-sex couples is basely unfair. To justify the restriction in our marriage laws by accusing the plaintiffs of attempting to change the institution of marriage itself, terminates the debate at the outset without any accompanying reasoned analysis.
[40]6
Justice Cordy's separate opinion points out, correctly, that, when art. 1 was
revised by the people in 1976, it was not then intended to be relied on to
approve same-sex marriage. Post at (Cordy, J., dissenting). (Justice Spina
adverts to the same proposition in his separate opinion, post at [Spina, J.,
dissenting]). Decisions construing the provision cited in Justice Cordy's
opinion are interesting, but obviously inapposite because they have not dealt in
any significant way with the issue before us. Nonetheless, the separate opinion
concludes, from what was intended in 1976, and from various cases discussing
art. 1, that the revised provision cannot be used to justify the result I reach.
In so reasoning, the separate opinion places itself squarely
on the side of the original intent school of constitutional interpretation. As a
general principle, I do not accept the philosophy of the school. The
Massachusetts Constitution was never meant to create dogma that adopts
inflexible views of one time to deny lawful rights to those who live in another.
The provisions of our Constitution are, and must be, adaptable to changing
circumstances and new societal phenomena, and, unless and until the people speak
again on a specific subject, conformable in their concepts of liberty and
equality to what is fair, right, and just. I am cognizant of the voters' intent
in passing the amendment to art. 1 in 1976. Were the revision alone the basis
for change, I would be reluctant to construe it favorably to the plaintiffs, in
view of the amendment's recent passage and the voters' intent. The court's
opinion, however, rests in part on well-established principles of equal
protection that are independent of the amendment. It is on these principles that
I base my opinion.
[41]1 Article 30 of the Massachusetts Declaration of Rights provides that "the judicial [department] shall never exercise the legislative and executive powers . . . to the end it may be a government of laws and not of men."
[42]2 Article 1 of the Massachusetts Declaration of Rights, as amended by art. 106 of the Amendments, the Equal Rights Amendment, states: "Equality under the law shall not be denied or abridged because of sex, race, color, creed or national origin."
[43]3 Marriage is the civil union between a single man and a single woman. See Milford v. Worcester, 7 Mass. 48, 52 (1810).
[44]1 The one difference that the court acknowledges -- that sexual relations between persons of the same sex does not result in pregnancy and childbirth -- it immediately brushes aside on the theory that civil marriage somehow has nothing to do with begetting children. Ante at - . For the reasons explained in detail in Justice Cordy's dissent, in which I join, the reasons justifying the civil marriage laws are inextricably linked to the fact that human sexual intercourse between a man and a woman frequently results in pregnancy and childbirth. Indeed, as Justice Cordy outlines, that fact lies at the core of why society fashioned the institution of marriage in the first place. Post at (Cordy, J., dissenting).
[45]1
The rational basis standard applied under the Massachusetts Constitution and the
Fourteenth Amendment to the United States Constitution is the same. See Chebacco
Liquor Mart, Inc. v. Alcoholic Beverages Control Comm'n, 429 Mass. 721, 722-723
(1999).
[46]2
The same semantic sleight of hand could transform every other restriction on
marriage into an infringement of a right of fundamental importance. For example,
if one assumes that a group of mature, consenting, committed adults can form a
"marriage," the prohibition on polygamy (G. L. c. 207,
§ 4), infringes on their "right" to "marry." In legal
analysis as in mathematics, it is fundamentally erroneous to assume the truth of
the very thing that is to be proved.
[47]3 Casting the right to civil marriage as a "fundamental right" in the constitutional sense is somewhat peculiar. It is not referred to as such in either the State or Federal Constitution, and unlike other recognized fundamental rights (such as the right to procreate, the right to be free of government restraint, or the right to refuse medical treatment), civil marriage is wholly a creature of State statute. If by enacting a civil marriage statutory scheme Massachusetts has created a fundamental right, then it could never repeal its own statute without violating the fundamental rights of its inhabitants.
[48]4 For example, see G. L. c. 272, §§ 14 and 18, the Massachusetts adultery and fornication statutes.
[49]5 While the facts of Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479 (1965), involved a married couple, later decisions clarify that its holding was not premised on the marriage relationship. See Carey v. Populations Servs. Int'l, 431 U.S. 678, 687 (1977) (stating that Griswold rested on the "right of the individual" to be free from governmental interference with child-bearing decisions [emphasis in original]); Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U.S. 438, 453-454 (1972) (same).
[50]6 Contrast Lawrence v. Texas, 123 S. Ct. 2472 (2003), in which the United States Supreme Court struck down the Texas criminal sodomy statute because it constituted State intrusion on some of these very choices.
[51]7 The statutes from which our current marriage laws derive were enacted prior to or shortly after the adoption of our Constitution in 1780, and "may well be considered . . . as affording some light in regard to the views and intentions of [the Constitution's] founders." Merriam v. Secretary of the Commonwealth, 375 Mass. 246, 253 (1978).
[52]8 Tobin's Case, 424 Mass. 250, 252-253 (1997) (no fundamental right to receive workers' compensation benefits); Doe v. Superintendent of Schs. of Worcester, 421 Mass. 117, 129 (1995) (no fundamental right to education); Williams v. Secretary of the Executive Office of Human Servs., 414 Mass. 551, 565 (1993) (no fundamental right to receive mental health services); Matter of Tocci, 413 Mass. 542, 548 n.4 (1992) (no fundamental right to practice law); Rushworth v. Registrar of Motor Vehicles, 413 Mass. 265, 269 n.5 (1992) (no fundamental right to operate motor vehicle); English v. New England Med. Ctr., Inc., 405 Mass. 423, 429 (1989), cert. denied, 493 U.S. 1056 (1990) (no fundamental right to recover tort damages); Commonwealth v. Henry's Drywall Co., 366 Mass. 539, 542 (1974) (no fundamental right to pursue one's business). Cf. Aime v. Commonwealth, 414 Mass. 667, 674 n.10 (1993) (recognizing right to be free from physical restraint "does not involve judicial derivation of controversial 'new' rights from the Constitution"). See generally Williams v. Secretary of the Executive Office of Human Servs., supra at 566 (recognizing fundamental right to receive mental health services "would represent an enormous and unwarranted extension of the judiciary into the [Department of Mental Health]'s authority"); Ford v. Grafton, 44 Mass. App. Ct. 715, 730-731, cert. denied, 525 U.S. 1040 (1998), quoting DeShaney v. Winnebago County Dep't of Social Servs., 489 U.S. 189, 203 (1989) ("people of Massachusetts may choose by legislation to [provide remedies for "grievous harm"] . . . however, 'they should not have [such remedies] thrust upon them by this Court's expansion of the Due Process Clause . . .").
[53]9 See Michael H. v. Gerald D., 491 U.S. 110, 122-123 & n.3, 127 (1989) (plurality opinion) (limits on substantive due process rights center on "respect for the teachings of history"); Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479, 501 (1965) (Harlan, J., concurring) (same).
[54]10 Compare Curtis v. School Comm. of Falmouth, 420 Mass. 749, 756 (1995), cert. denied, 516 U.S. 1067 (1996), quoting Wisconsin v. Yoder, 406 U.S. 205, 232 (1972) ("primary role of the parents in the upbringing of their children is now established beyond debate as an enduring American tradition"); Aime v. Commonwealth, supra at 676 ("right to be free from governmental detention and restraint is firmly embedded in the history of Anglo-American law"); Brophy v. New England Sinai Hosp., Inc., 398 Mass. 417, 430 (1986) (right to make decisions to accept or reject medical treatment "has its roots deep in our history" and "has come to be widely recognized and respected"); and Moe v. Secretary of Admin. & Fin., 382 Mass. 629, 649 (1981) (characterizing decision whether to bear a child as "hold[ing] a particularly important place in the history of the right of privacy" and finding "something approaching consensus" on right to refuse unwanted infringement of bodily integrity), with Trigones v. Attorney Gen., 420 Mass. 859, 863 (1995), quoting Medina v. California, 505 U.S. 437, 445 (1992) (upholding statute that does not "offend some principle of justice so rooted in the tradition and conscience of our people as to be ranked fundamental"); Three Juveniles v. Commonwealth, 390 Mass. 357, 364 (1983), cert. denied sub nom. Keefe v. Massachusetts, 465 U.S. 1068 (1984) (declining to find fundamental right to child-parent privilege where "[n]either Congress nor the Legislature of any State has seen fit to adopt a rule granting [such] a privilege . . ."); Commonwealth v. Stowell, 389 Mass. 171, 174 (1983), quoting Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113, 152 (1973) (declining to recognize right not "implicit in the concept of ordered liberty").
[55]11 Because of the absence of deep historical roots, every court but one that has considered recognizing a fundamental right to same-sex marriage, has declined to do so. See, e.g., Standhardt v. Superior Court, 77 P.3d 451 (Ariz. Ct. App. 2003); Dean v. District of Columbia, 653 A.2d 307, 333 (D.C. 1995) (per curiam) (Ferren, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part); Baehr v. Lewin, 74 Haw. 530, 556-557 (1993); Baker v. Nelson, 291 Minn. 310, 312-314 (1971); Storrs v. Holcomb, 168 Misc. 2d 898, 899-900 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. 1996), dismissed, 245 A.D.2d 943 (N.Y. 1997). The one exception was the Alaska Superior Court, which relied on that State's Constitution's express and broadly construed right to privacy. Brause vs. Bureau of Vital Statistics, No. 3AN-95-6562CJ (Alaska Super. Ct. Feb. 27, 1998).
[56]12 Article 106 is referred to as the Equal Rights Amendment.
[57]13 Justice Greaney views Loving v. Virginia, 388 U.S. 1 (1967), as standing analogously for the proposition that just as a person cannot be barred from marrying another person because of his or her race, a person cannot be barred from marrying another person because of his or her sex. Ante at (Greaney, J., concurring). While superficially attractive, this analogy does not withstand closer scrutiny. Unlike Virginia's antimiscegenation statute, neither the purpose nor effect of the Massachusetts marriage statute is to advantage or disadvantage one gender over the other. This distinction is critical and was central to the Loving decision. More fundamentally, the statute at issue burdened marriage with a requirement that was both constitutionally suspect and unrelated to protecting either the underlying purposes or nature of the institution. In contrast, the limitation of marriage to one man and one woman preserves both its structure and its historic purposes.
[58]14 The commission was composed of five State representatives, three State senators and three gubernatorial appointees. All of the gubernatorial appointees were attorneys.
[59]15 The Washington case cited by the commission was Singer v. Hara, 11 Wash. App. 247 (1974).
[60]16 Modern DNA testing may reveal actual paternity, but it establishes only a genetic relationship between father and child.
[61]17 The normative relationship between husband and wife has changed markedly due to the overwhelming movement toward gender equality both at home and in the marketplace.
[62]18 The availability of a variety of social welfare programs and public education has in many instances affected the status of the marital family as the only environment dedicated to the care, protection, and education of children.
[63]19 No-fault divorce has made the dissolution of marriage much easier than ever before.
[64]20 "It is important to distinguish the individual interests in domestic relations from the social interest in the family and marriage as social institutions." Pound, Individual Interests in the Domestic Relations, 14 Mich. L. Rev. 177, 177 (1916). The court's opinion blurs this important distinction and emphasizes the personal and emotional dimensions that often accompany marriage. It is, however, only society's interest in the institution of marriage as a stabilizing social structure that justifies the statutory benefits and burdens that attend to the status provided by its laws. Personal fulfilment and public celebrations or announcements of commitment have little if anything to do with the purpose of the civil marriage laws, or with a legitimate public interest that would justify them.
[65]21 In support of its conclusion that the marriage statute does not satisfy the rational basis test, the court emphasizes that "[t]he department has offered no evidence that forbidding marriage to people of the same sex will increase the number of couples choosing to enter into opposite-sex marriages in order to have and raise children." Ante at . This surprising statement misallocates the burden of proof in a constitutional challenge to the rational basis of a statute (see supra at - ). It is the plaintiffs who must prove that supporting and promoting one form of relationship by providing (as is pointed out) literally hundreds of benefits, could not conceivably affect the decision-making of anyone considering whether to bear and raise a child. The department is not required to present "evidence" of anything.
[66]22 See C.N. Degler, The Emergence of the Modern American Family, in The American Family in Social-Historical Perspective 61 (3d ed. 1983); A.J. Hawkins, Introduction, in Revitalizing the Institution of Marriage for the Twenty-First Century: An Agenda for Strengthening Marriage xiv (2002); C. Lasch, Social Pathologists and the Socialization of Reproduction, in The American Family in Social-Historical Perspective, 80 (3d ed. 1983); W.J. O'Donnell & D.A. Jones, The Law of Marriage and Marital Alternatives 1 (1982); L. Saxton, The Individual, Marriage and the Family 229-230, 260 (1968); M.A. Schwartz & B.M. Scott, Marriages and Families: Diversity and Change 4 (1994); Wardle, "Multiply and Replenish": Considering Same-Sex Marriage in Light of State Interests in Marital Procreation, 24 Harv. J.L. & Pub. Pol'y 771, 777-780 (2001); J.Q. Wilson, The Marriage Problem: How Our Culture has Weakened Families 28, 40, 66-67 (2002).
[67]23 See Rodney, Behavioral Differences between African American Male Adolescents with Biological Fathers and Those Without Biological Fathers in the Home, 30 J. Black Stud. 45, 53 (1999) (African-American juveniles who lived with their biological fathers displayed fewer behavioral problems than those whose biological fathers were absent from home); Chilton, Family Disruption, Delinquent Conduct and the Effect of Subclassification, 37 Am. Soc. Rev. 93, 95 (1972) (proportion of youth charged with juvenile offenses who were not living in husband-wife family was larger than comparable proportion of youth charged with juvenile offenses who were living in husband-wife family); Hoffmann, A National Portrait of Family Structure and Adolescent Drug Use, 60 J. Marriage & Fam. 633 (1998) (children from households with both mother and father reported relatively low use of drugs, whereas children from households without their natural mothers and from other family type households had highest prevalence of drug use). See also D. Blankenhorn, Fatherless America: Confronting Our Most Urgent Social Problem 25 (1995).
[68]24 H.B. Biller & J.L. Kimpton, The Father and the School-Aged Child, in The Role of The Father in Child Development 143 (3d ed. 1997); H.B. Biller, Fathers and Families: Paternal Factors in Child Development 1-3 (1993); Lynne Marie Kohm, The Homosexual "Union": Should Gay and Lesbian Partnerships be Granted the Same Status as Marriage? 22 J. Contemp. L. 51, 61 & nn.53, 54 (1996) ("[s]tatistics continue to show that the most stable family for children to grow up in is that consisting of a father and a mother").
[69]25 See, e.g., Patterson, Family Relationships of Lesbians and Gay Men, 62 J. Marriage & Fam. 1052, 1060, 1064-1065 (2000) (concluding that there are no significant differences between children of same-sex parents and children of heterosexual parents in aspects of personal development).
[70]26 See, e.g., Cameron, Homosexual Parents, 31 Adolescence 757, 770-774 (1996) (concluding results of limited study consonant with notion that children raised by homosexuals disproportionately experience emotional disturbance and sexual victimization).
[71]27 See, e.g., Stacey, (How) Does the Sexual Orientation of Parents Matter?, 66 Amer. Soc. Rev. 159, 172, 176-179 (2001) (finding significant statistical differences in parenting practices, gender roles, sexual behavior but noting that "heterosexism" and political implications have constrained research). See also Coleman, Reinvestigating Remarriage: Another Decade of Progress, 62 J. Marriage & Fam. 1288 (2000) (concluding that future studies of impact of divorce and remarriage on children should focus on "nontraditional" stepfamilies, particularly same-sex couples with children, because impact of such arrangements have been overlooked in other studies).
[72]28 In Massachusetts, for example, the State's adoption laws were only recently interpreted to permit adoption by same-sex partners. Adoption of Tammy, 416 Mass. 205 (1993). It is fair to assume that most of the children affected by that ruling, who properly would be the subject of study in their teenage and adult years, are still only children today.
[73]29 This family structure raises the prospect of children lacking any parent of their own gender. For example, a boy raised by two lesbians as his parents has no male parent. Contrary to the suggestion that concerns about such a family arrangement is based on "stereotypical" views about the differences between sexes, ante at n.28, concern about such an arrangement remains rational. It is, for example, rational to posit that the child himself might invoke gender as a justification for the view that neither of his parents "understands" him, or that they "don't know what he is going through," particularly if his disagreement or dissatisfaction involves some issue pertaining to sex. Given that same-sex couples raising children are a very recent phenomenon, the ramifications of an adolescent child's having two parents but not one of his or her own gender have yet to be fully realized and cannot yet even be tested in significant numbers. But see note 25, supra, regarding studies of children raised without parents of each gender.
[74]30 The same could be true of any other potentially promising but recent innovation in the relationships of persons raising children.
[75]31 The plaintiffs also argue that because the State requires insurance companies to provide coverage for diagnosing and treating infertility unrestricted to those who are married, G. L. c. 175, § 47H, limiting marriage to opposite-sex couples is contrary to its currently stated public policy, and, therefore no longer rational. This argument is not persuasive. The fact that the Legislature has seen fit to require that health insurers cover the medical condition of infertility, for all subscribers, is not inconsistent with the State's policy of encouraging and endorsing heterosexual marriage as the optimum structure in which to bear and raise children. There is no rule that requires the State to limit every law bearing on birth and child rearing to the confines of heterosexual marriage in order to vindicate its policy of supporting that structure as optimal. Just as the insurance laws relating to infertility coverage cannot be said to be a State endorsement of childbirth out of wedlock, they cannot be said to represent an abandonment of the State's policy regarding a preference that children be born into and raised in the context of heterosexual marriage.
[76]32 Indeed, just recently, this court reasoned that the Legislature could permissibly conclude that children being raised by single parents "may be at heightened risk for certain kinds of harm when compared with children of so-called intact families," because such children "may not have or be able to draw on the resources of two parents" when having to cope with some form of loss. Blixt v. Blixt, 437 Mass. 649, 663, 664 (2002), cert. denied, 537 U.S. 1189 (2003). In that case, the differences between single parents and parents raising a child together sufficed to justify subjecting single parents to the grandparent visitation statute, G. L. c. 119, § 39D. Id. at 662-664. Because the statute implicated fundamental parental rights, its classifications had to survive strict scrutiny, id. at 660, not the mere rational basis test at issue in today's opinion. The fact that single people can adopt children did not insulate them from differential treatment with respect to their parental rights.
[77]33 Similarly, while the fact that our laws have evolved to include a strong affirmative policy against discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation, have decriminalized intimate adult conduct, and have abolished the legal distinctions between marital and nonmarital children, may well be a reason to celebrate a more open and humane society, they ought not be the basis on which to conclude that there is no longer a rational basis for the current marriage law. See ante at . To conclude the latter based on the former threatens the process of social reform in a democratic society. States must be free to experiment in the realm of social and civil relations, incrementally and without concern that a step or two in one direction will determine the outcome of the experiment as a matter of law. If they are not, those who argue "slippery slope" will have more ammunition than ever to resist any effort at progressive change or social experimentation, and will be able to put the lie to the arguments of the proponents of such efforts, that an incremental step forward does not preordain a result which neither the people nor their elected representatives may yet be prepared to accept.
[78]34
The court contends that the exclusive and permanent commitment of the marriage
partnership rather than the begetting of children is the sine qua non of civil
marriage, ante at , and that "the 'marriage is procreation' argument
singles out the one unbridgeable difference between same-sex and opposite-sex
couples, and transforms that difference into the essence of legal
marriage." Ante at . The court has it backward. Civil marriage is the
product of society's critical need to manage procreation as the inevitable
consequence of intercourse between members of the opposite sex. Procreation has
always been at the root of marriage and the reasons for its existence as a
social institution. Its structure, one man and one woman committed for life,
reflects society's judgment as how optimally to manage procreation and the
resultant child rearing. The court, in attempting to divorce procreation from
marriage, transforms the form of the structure into its purpose. In doing so, it
turns history on its head.
The court compounds its error by likening the marriage statute
to Colorado's "Amendment 2" which was struck by the United States
Supreme Court in Romer v. Evans, 517 U.S. 620, 633 (1996). That amendment
repealed all Colorado laws and ordinances that barred discrimination against
homosexuals, and prohibited any governmental entity from adopting similar
statutes. The amendment withdrew from homosexuals, but no others, legal
protection from a broad range of injuries caused by private and governmental
discrimination, "imposing a broad and undifferentiated disability on a
single named group." Id. at 632. As the Court noted, its sheer breadth
seems "inexplicable by anything but animus toward the class it
affects." Id. The comparison to the Massachusetts marriage statute, which
limits the institution of marriage (created to manage procreation) to
opposite-sex couples who can theoretically procreate, is completely inapposite.
[79]35 Although the marriage statute is overinclusive because it comprehends within its scope infertile or voluntarily nonreproductive opposite-sex couples, this overinclusiveness does not make the statute constitutionally infirm. See Massachusetts Fed'n of Teachers v. Board of Educ., 436 Mass. 763, 778 (2002) ("Some degree of overinclusiveness or underinclusiveness is constitutionally permissible . . ."). The overinclusiveness present here is constitutionally permissible because the Commonwealth has chosen, reasonably, not to test every prospective married couple for fertility and not to demand of fertile prospective married couples whether or not they will procreate. It is satisfied, rather, to allow every couple whose biological opposition makes procreation theoretically possible to join the institution.
[80]36 Concerns about such unintended consequences cannot be dismissed as fanciful or far-fetched. Legislative actions taken in the 1950's and 1960's in areas as widely arrayed as domestic relations law and welfare legislation have had significant unintended adverse consequences in subsequent decades including the dramatic increase in children born out of wedlock, and the destabilization of the institution of marriage. See Nonmarital Childbearing in the United States 1940-99, National Center for Health Statistics, 48 Nat'l Vital Stat. Reps. at 2 (Oct. 2000) (nonmarital childbirths increased from 3.8% of annual births in 1940 to 33% in 1999); M.D. Bramlett, Cohabitation, Marriage, Divorce, and Remarriage in the United States, National Center for Health Statistics, Vital & Health Stat. at 4-5 (July 2002) (due to higher divorce rates and postponement of marriage, proportion of people's lives spent in marriage declined significantly during later half of Twentieth Century).
[81]37 "[T]he State retains wide latitude to decide the manner in which it will allocate benefits." Moe v. Secretary of Admin. & Fin., 382 Mass. 629, 652 (1981). To the extent that the Legislature concludes that one form of social relationship is more optimal than another for the bearing and raising of children, it is free to promote and support the one and not the other, so long as its conclusion is rational, and does not discriminatorily burden the exercise of a fundamental right. Id. Cf. Rust v. Sullivan, 500 U.S. 173, 192-193 (1991) ("Government can, without violating the Constitution, selectively fund a program to encourage certain activities it believes to be in the public interest, without at the same time funding an alternative program which seeks to deal with the problems in another way").
[82]38 Legislatures in many parts of the country continue to consider various means of affording same-sex couples the types of benefits and legal structures that married couples enjoy. For example, in 1999 the California Legislature established the first Statewide domestic partner registry in the nation, and in each of the years 2001, 2002, and 2003 substantially expanded the rights and benefits accruing to registered partners. Cal. Fam. Code §§ 297 et seq. (West Supp. 2003). See also comments of Massachusetts Senate President Robert Traviglini to the effect that he intends to bring civil union legislation to the floor of the Senate for a vote. Mass. Senate Eyes Civil Unions: Move Comes as SJC Mulls Gay Marriages, Boston Globe, Sept. 7, 2003, at A1.